City University of New York (CUNY) City University of New York (CUNY)
CUNY Academic Works CUNY Academic Works
Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects CUNY Graduate Center
9-2019
What Rome Really Adopted from Ancient Greece What Rome Really Adopted from Ancient Greece
Christian J. Vella
The Graduate Center, City University of New York
How does access to this work bene;t you? Let us know!
More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/3450
Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu
This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY).
Contact: AcademicWorks@cuny.edu
WHAT ROME REALLY ADOPTED FROM ANCIENT GREECE
by
CHRISTIAN VELLA
A thesis submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Liberal Studies in partial satisfaction of the requirements
for the degree of Master of Arts, The City University of New York
2019
© 2019
CHRISTIAN VELLA
All Rights Reserved
ii
Western Philosophical Tradition : What Rome really adopted from Greece
A Research Study
by
Christian Vella
This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Liberal
Studies in satisfaction of the thesis requirement for the degree of Master of Arts.
Date Marie Marianetti
Advisor
Date Elizabeth Macaulay-Lewis
Executive Officer
THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK
iii
Abstract
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
by
Christian Vella
Advisor : Marie Marianetti
The Roman conquest of the Greek city-states and the appropriation of many aspects of its
culture, especially architecture and art, is well known. But what of the many great philosophies that
began in the various city-states of Ancient Greece? This piece is made in attempt to answer this
question. The scope of these sources will start with the beginning of the Western Philosophical
Tradition, with Thales of Miletus and the Milesian, all the way up to, but not including, the foundation
of the Christian Philosophical Tradition. After the year 146 BC if a philosopher is born in a Greek-City
state, they are to be considered Roman due to their induction into the Roman civilization. To this end,
this text will be using translated original philosophical pieces, biographical articles and pieces, relevant
historical data, and collected overviews of philosophical schools as sources. Using these sources the
philosophies of Ancient Greece will each be described and have a representative appointed or each of
them. Following this, the same procedure will be undertaken for the philosophies of Ancient Rome.
After the outlining of these philosophies they will then be brought into comparison with one another,
trying to track the lineage of a philosophy if possible, or even pairing up possibly unrelated
philosophies that share distinct similarities. It is then that the philosophies will be compared and
contrasted, their differences and similarities brought into light and reflected on before a final
conclusion as to what Ancient Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece is drawn.
iv
Table of Contents
Page
Cover Page...................................................................................................................................................
Copyright Declaration. .............................................................................................................................. ii
Abstract .................................................................................................................................................... iv
Table of Contents ...................................................................................................................................... v
Introduction ............................................................................................................................................... 1
Ancient Greek Philosophy ........................................................................................................................ 9
Ancient Roman Philosophy .................................................................................................................... 46
Comparing Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome ...................................................................................... 69
Conclusion .............................................................................................................................................. 92
Bibliography ........................................................................................................................................... 99
v
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
1
Introduction
Contemporary ideologies and philosophies are rarely, if ever, spontaneously generated. They
are instead heavily influenced by the many millennia of human history, technological discoveries, then
recent circumstances, and the development of culture. Western civilization as a whole can trace itself
back to the machinations and the works of antiquity, particularly to that of the ancient Greek and
Roman civilizations. It is through the discoveries and inventions of the classical civilizations that the
modern day eventually arose.
Ancient Greece
The first Western Philosopher is claimed to be Thales of the Greek city-state of Miletus. With
Thales was established a tradition of exploration and speculation of the human sphere, the natural
world, and speculation into the metaphysical and ethereal beyond. From this inquiry and desire to
understand would arise the sciences, both the social sciences and the natural sciences, and academia.
Educational systems would be founded by and refined by philosophers, with tutoring being exemplified
by the Sophists, the Platonic Academy giving rise to higher level education along with the Lyceum of
Aristotle. The Pythagoreans pushed ancient Greece further towards greater mathematical understanding
of the universe, an understanding similar to that which is held today in the natural sciences. Athens in
particular was held as a forum for intellectuals to congregate, learn and debate, attracting some of the
greatest philosophers the ancient world had to offer, in particular Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. These
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
2
three philosophers would change how the western world approached the world, understanding and
wisdom in general, with Aristotle being dubbed 'The Philosopher' to many.
The variety existing in the many city-states of Ancient Greece and their exposure with other
civilizations around the Mediterranean fueled their exploration of various political systems. From the
Spartan Diarchy to the Athenian Democracy and various other systems utilized, the intellectuals of the
ancient world had much to mull and ponder over. There was great consideration of morality, the nature
of society, and political theory as can be seen in a variety of pieces that have survived. In regards to the
social sciences and the study of culture and proper codes of conduct, there is also the Cynical tradition
being born in ancient Greece, seeking to undermine all forms of convention, and the Sophistic and
Aristotelian focus on forms of argumentation via rhetoric, and the many Pythagorean rituals and codes
of conduct.
Along with a rich exposure to human nature in the form of governmental types they had a deep
desire to understand the world around them, and in particular the worlds above them. Many
philosophers sought to understand the universe in a variety of means, from the mystical and mythical to
the attempts at proto-scientific natural sciences with what tools they had available at the time.
Pythagoras sought to explain the universe mathematically, Democritus and Epicurus with theories of
matter and void, Socrates and Plato with an understanding of metaphysical Forms, and various other
philosophers seeking an elemental base to the universe. Their pursuits often lead to seemingly bizarre
statements, such as Zeno of Elea and his denial of motion and movement as recounted by Aristotle.
While many of their theories regarding the ontology of the universe or the functioning of those that lie
within are demonstrably false, there is still much to glean regarding the reasoning that lead them to
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
3
their understandings and the repercussions of said understanding.
Of course the Greek city-states were a relatively small cluster of civilizations. Their intellectual
scope was limited and their utility as a forum for the development and refining of their philosophies
was subsequently also limited. Considering the cultural similarities between the Greek city-states and
the historical and linguistic commonalities that bring them together, despite the many feuds that have
occurred across their history, they will be spoken of in this piece as a collective civilization. As
juxtaposition the contemporary intellectual fields, as many other things in the 21st century, are
remarkably globalized, having to be put in contest with innumerable other philosophies, cultures, and
religions.
Ancient Rome
The Ancient Romans are known for not only adopting a large amount of Greek culture via their
religion but also their philosophy, having translated much of the original philosophical transcriptions
from Greek to Latin in order to preserve them. One of the most obvious aspects of the Greek culture
that the Romans appropriated was their religion, adopting and renaming many of the Hellenic gods and
keeping the many myths surrounding them. Along with this, the Romans adopted Greek architectural
and artistic styling. From everything the Romans adopted from the Greek, arguably the most important
and influential aspect they derived from the Greek were their philosophies. The Platonic Academy, its
Skeptics and Platonists, the Cynics, the Stoics, the Epicureans and even the Pythagoreans found their
ways into the Roman empire. It is within the Roman civilization that these philosophies discovered an
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
4
entirely new form of intellectual exposure.
So important was philosophy to the Romans that even one of their emperors, Marcus Aurelius
Antoninus Augustus, was heralded as a philosopher king (the likes of which described in the Socratic
text of The Republic). Marcus Aurelius is considered one of the greatest and more influential Stoic
philosophers in history, with his text The Meditations being the primary piece of literature he left
behind to reveal his inner understanding and thoughts towards his philosophy. Philosophy flourished in
the Roman Empire, particularly that of the Stoic and the Epicurean schools. The following of many
schools increased significantly.
Thanks to the structure of the Roman empire, being vast and various peoples, cultures,
religions, and ideologies, the ancient Greek philosophies would receive exposure but also be tested.
While a number of Greek philosophies expanded their following and literature within the Roman
civilization, other philosophies fell by the wayside and into historical obscurity. The various Milesian
schools, the Pyrrhonian school, along with several others found themselves having no philosophers or
writers upholding their philosophy.
It is in the massive, multicultural, and multiethnic Roman Empire that ideologies would truly be
put through the test to see if they could survive the intense competition. Stoicism and Epicureanism
were greatly favored, taking their place next to the Aristotelian Peripatetics and Platonism in the
renewed Platonic Academy in Athens.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
5
Inciting Question
The question then arises: What exactly shifted, ideologically and philosophically, between the
Greek and Roman civilizations? Was it an adoption and name change (followed by expansion and
development), like what happened to the Ancient Greek Mythology and Religion? Was it a shift of
focus, raising some ideologies to higher popularity based on preference, utility, or some other factor?
Did the ideologies substantially change or develop? Would they remain recognizable to their founders?
Did they keep the superficial or early theories the same but, with time and study, have drastically
unforeseen conclusions?
The field of philosophy is an ever changing one, with both debate between the various
ideologies within it and with the ever increasing examination of said ideologies. While the ancient
philosophers set the groundwork for their theories it is their followers that often had to examine
increasingly specific circumstances, testing the evidence presented, and often ultimately grasping
conclusions that could be considered strange or outlandish. One such example can be found in the
Socratic understanding of reality, speaking of a Realm of True Forms, which lead to many different
understandings for various different ideologies that would develop from the philosophy of Socrates.
Methodology
To properly gain perspective and understanding about these ancient and complex philosophies,
this piece will examine multiple different sources. Firstly, translations of the primary pieces will be
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
6
held to scrutiny. While many of the primary documents have been lost to time for a number of reasons,
a number of them have been preserved in transcriptions and translations over the years. Translations,
unfortunately, do not always carry the same intended meaning as in their original language, but that is
inherent to all translations and is often mitigated by offering multiple translations for obscure or
technical words and terminology, or leaving the word untranslated and instead defining it. 'Arche', for
example, has no equivalent in English and is instead treated as a term rather than a properly translated
word. These translated pieces would not be merely held at face value, research would also be
undertaken to see the historical significance of their various analogies and the people who allegedly
partook in it (if it's a dialogue or recreation of a scene).
Secondly, secondary sources will also be utilized. Collective studies, either regarding an entire
philosophical school across time and across its various representatives or a compilations of an entire
person's life, will be utilized. That, with cross references to relevant historical events and
developments, allows for a greater generalized understanding of said philosophies and philosophers.
There are a considerable number of pieces lost to time with the only evidence of their existence being
reference to them in other documents. These references come in the form of commentaries,
philosophers mentioning other pieces in their own piece in order to examine their philosophy or for
purpose of juxtaposition. Aristotle famously refers to many other philosophical schools throughout his
his works, assisting in contemporary scholars' understanding of the schools even with lost texts.
Additionally, biographical information of these philosophers can assist in theorizing what they
could have been exposed to, which in turn may have influenced their philosophy. One such example of
exposure would be with Pyrrho of Elis, who traveled to the Middle-East and met with the
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
7
Gymnosophists and Zoroastrian Magi, which may have in turn influenced his perception and
understanding of reality. Exposure to various philosophical schools, religions, cultures, fields and
methods of study, even war and natural phenomena can affect how people approach their
understanding of the world around them.
While these Ancient Philosophies will have theological and religious connotations to them we
will refrain from examining explicit religions, and as such will end our review before the rise of the
early Christian philosophies. In order to have a proper scope for this review excluding Christianity will
assist in keeping the philosophies distinctly in the age of Antiquity. The second reason is the mitigating
factor of faith in religion, one which does not operate so firmly in philosophy. The third reason is due
to the more dogmatic tendencies that tend to be exhibited in religions. This is something that would
discourage discourse and argumentation, two things vital for the exploration of a philosophical system.
It is with this approach and understanding that the study of the Ancient Greek and Roman
schools will be undertaken. The philosophical schools will be identified, their fundamental
philosophical topics and stances be explained, and a representative of their school will be selected in
order for more specific attempts to understand their school. The use of a representative is to better
allow peer to peer comparison between the philosophies across time, to see how stances have shifted
and developed, if at all, and to lessen the likelihood of contradiction within a school that would occur
by taking into account as many representatives as possible. The selection of representatives of the
schools was based on a variety of factors, including the personal following of the philosopher, how
prolific they were in regards to their pieces (be it verbal or written), whether or not they founded their
school (a founder being close to the original tenants and focus of said school), and how influential they
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
8
were to the other members of their school, to name a few variables.
First the Ancient Greek will be taken into consideration. A Greek representative would be
selected from each school. This is due to their civilization being older and also because they are later
captured by the Roman Empire, and as such becoming exposed to the Roman civilization, necessarily
ushering their intellectuals into a new circumstance. Following the examination of the Ancient Greek
philosophies will come an examination of Ancient Roman Philosophies, to see which schools
continued to exist or emerged within the Roman Empire. A Roman representative would be selected for
each school, even if they already had a Greek representative selected.
Finally there will be comparisons drawn between the philosophies that persisted between the
two civilizations, but also an examination of their successor or 'descendant' philosophies. One such
example could be seen between the Greek Platonists and the Roman Middle Platonists, Middle
Platonism easily being considered a 'descendant' of the Ancient Greek Platonism, but not the only one.
The philosophy of Socrates was responsible for a large variety of schools in one way or another, either
as continuations of aspects of his own philosophy or as a reaction and rejection of his beliefs.
Following the comparison a conclusion will be drawn, both regarding a comparison of the philosophies
of Ancient Greek and Ancient Rome and what factors were most likely responsible for the difference or
similarity of the philosophies.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
9
Ancient Greek Philosophy
Within the bounds of the feuding Ancient Greek city-states lies what is considered the
beginning of Western Philosophy, starting with Thales of Miletus and carrying on a tradition that has
helped guide the course of history. While the many different city-states were distinct with different
political regimes and other variances there were common notions of culture, inter-city activity (like the
Olympics), common religious beliefs across the region, a common language, and a common notion of
heritage. There will be philosophers from these city-states considered Roman within this piece due to
them being born after 146 BC, considering they would then be part of the Roman civilization.
Pre-Socratic Philosophy
The Metaphysical/Physical Theories and Distinctions
Long before the 'divine' task set upon Socrates to justify his title of wisest of all men given to
him by 'the Goddess', there were those who also had a love of wisdom. The first recorded western
philosopher is believed to be Thales of Miletus, as identified by Aristotle. Due to the great influence
Socrates had to the field of philosophy those of the western philosophical tradition that operated before
Socrates are collectively referred to as “Pre-Socratic”. These Pre-Socratic philosophers sought that
same things that later philosophers would seek; explanations for reality and the world around them,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
10
understanding for things both perceptible and imperceptible, and how best should humans conduct
themselves?
Before delving into this, clarification is needed regarding the 'Metaphysical/Physical' term being
used. Considering one of the fields of studies within Philosophy is that of metaphysics, the study of the
essence of reality. The term has developed an association between metaphysical things being extra-
physical, super-physical, supernatural, or non-physical. Considering many of these philosophies do not
explicitly believe in something metaphysical in a non-physical sense, especially those philosophies that
focus on Arches, elemental basis for reality, they deposit a firmly Physicalist theory of reality.
Physicalism being the stance in metaphysics that there really is no such metaphysics, that reality is
explicitly, primarily (or, more often, entirely) comprised of physical matter, whatever form it may take.
For the upcoming Ionians it takes the form of elements, transmuting and shifting. For the Atomists it
takes the form of matter and void. Other philosophies, such as that of Xenophanes, Plato, and even
more modern philosophers such as George Berkeley, believe reality to not be physically substantiated
but metaphysically so. That would mean that physical reality, as presented, is either a product of or a
misconception of metaphysical reality.
Ionian Schools
Milesians
The Milesian School, possibly the first philosophical school in the western world and Europe,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
11
was founded by Thales. The main function of this school was to try to find explanation for the world.
To this end they would engage in somewhat scientific philosophical examination and observation, often
dubbed metaphysical naturalists. Rather than being a school unified by a cohesive ideology they could
be more easily described as a school connected by tradition of methodology or by development on past
works. Thales of Miletus is famously known for believing that the fundamental prime element, or
'Arche', is water, claiming that all other elements and configurations of reality arise from the flowing
nature of water. Anaximander, Thales' student and successor, opposed him in this stance. The reason
being was that opposites could not arise from their opposition. Fire, having a nature antithesis to water,
could not arise from water. Anaximander held that none of the elements (air, earth, fire, and water)
could be the 'Arche' because of this, naming a substance he called 'Apeiron', an infinite substance, to be
the 'Arche'. The qualities of 'Apeiron' was that it was infinite and eternal, from which all things arise
and subsequently return to. Anaximander was then followed by his student, Anaximenes, who
concluded that Air was the 'Arche', citing divine qualities to it and explaining how air could rarify into
Fire, condense into the other elements in the pattern of wind, then cloud, then water, then earth, and
then stone. In that way Anaximenes explained the order of all things in reality, possibly acting as a
minor allegory to explain phenomena like density.
Heraclitus of Ephesus
Heraclitus of Ephesus had an influential philosophy of his own that deserves mention among
the Pre-Socratics. Like the Milesian school, Heraclitus was interested in the metaphysical and physical
composition of reality, and additionally had an interest in the moral affairs of humanity. Heraclitus held
that the 'Arche' was Fire, and attributed reality to be in an eternal state of change and flux, one that was
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
12
ushered ever onwards by fire and heat. This eternal change was subject to a pattern that he dubbed
Logos, being the pattern of change in reality. This change is greatly emphasized in the phrase ‘No man
ever steps in the same river twice, for it's not the same river and he's not the same man.’ , a turn of
phrase commonly attributed to Heraclitus. This phrase is derived from Plato’s analysis of Heraclitus,
being "Heraclitus, I believe, says that all things go and nothing stays, and comparing existents to the
flow of a river, he says you could not step twice into the same river" (Graham, D.W., n.d., Heraclitus) ,
What Heraclitus actually says is the following: On those stepping into rivers staying the same other
and other waters flow.”(Graham, D.W., n.d., Heraclitus) This understanding also lead to Heraclitus'
understanding of moral philosophy and justice, that in the change of all things the preservation of
constancy is impossible and that existence is a series of ascension and building followed by erosion and
degradation. This observation of Heraclitus regarding the fleeting and eroding nature of all things is in
part is what lead to his fabled somber disposition and subsequently his pseudonym ‘The Weeping
Philosopher’.
The Milesian School, its subsequent followers, and the studies of Heraclitus are collectively
referred to as the Ionian school. While the individual theories vary between the individuals of the
Ionian school they do have the tradition of iteration off of one another and the attempt to figure out the
'Arche', or primary element, that comprised reality.
Eleatics
The Eleatic School, founded by Parmenides of Elea, was a school focused on metaphysical
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
13
idealism. Metaphysical Idealism, in contrast to metaphysical Physicalism/Materialism, puts forward
that reality is primarily comprised of non-material components, specifically of notions and thoughts.
The Eleatics held that reality was within 'the One'. The theory of 'The One' was that of both a hierarchy
of reality (being from most real to least real), and the one entity or phenomenon that sits atop that
hierarchy. Additionally the Eleatics believed in the stillness and unity of all things. To them there is no
such thing as creation, and there is no arising, for reality exists as a constant with only superficial
deception tricking the senses of living things. Zeno of Elea, one of the schools most famous
representatives, brought awareness to his philosophy and the issue of the 'impossibility of movement'
with his many famous paradoxes. The paradoxes are more or less repetitious, expressing how an
objection, to reach its destination, continually has to traverse half of its remaining journey, and then
half again, infinitely. With the infinite potential for fractal numbers in mathematics the issue then arises
of the subject never reaching their goal, only coming very close. The progression goes : half, three
fourths, seven eighths, fifteen sixteenths, ad infinitum. They stood in stark opposition to Heraclitus.
These notions would not remain only within the Eleatic schools. The Notion of a 'The One' is not
unique to the Eleatics, something that the Neopythagoreans and eventually the Neoplatonists would
also hold, along with the deceptive nature of existence.
Atomists
The Atomist school was founded by Leucippus and his student Democritus, though Democritus
is the more well known of the two. The Atomist school is founded on the theory of Atoms. Unlike the
particles that share the name, the Atom theory was one in which there were indivisible, indestructible,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
14
and imperceptibly small particles that comprised physical reality. Additionally these particles would
not inherently have qualities of their own that their larger materials may have, and hence allow for
shifting from one type to another. The Atomist school is not Monistic (believing everything to be of
one type or element) in its metaphysics, believing there to also be something they’d refer to as Void.
Void to the Atomists was empty space, not occupied by any physical stances, and was essential to their
understanding of how the atoms interacted with one another. While this can be taken for granted in
contemporary physical understandings, it is not a given in ancient times. There were other Physicalists
that did not include void as part of their theories, sometimes even attempting to refute it outright. Void
allows for the atoms and larger structures that are comprised of atoms to move and shift, allowing for
there to be change and movement in reality. Also the nature of atoms not having inherent qualities that
the elements do, like heat or moisture, prevents the backlash suffered by the various elemental
monisms, since from the atoms no opposites arose. While the various Atomists may have had personal
ethical theories, as Democritus did, it was not inherent to the Atomist school that brought them together
and as such will not be mentioned in tandem with their collective school.
While the Atomist school may not have persisted very far in history, its influence was far felt,
having resonance with philosophers such as Plato and Epicurus. In fact the Epicurean metaphysics is
vitally similar to that of the Atomist school, believing too in base matter and void comprising reality.
As evidence to this being a crucial aspect of Epicureanism, rather than a personal belief of Epicurus
that may have been put by the wayside in favor of his ethics, the Atomistic universal structure
continued even into Rome, spread by others such as Titus Lucretius Carus.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
15
Pythagoreanism
Pythagoreanism was founded by Pythagoras of Samos, a remarkable Greek Philosopher and
Mathematician. His philosophical interests had a strong focus on metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics.
Unlike other philosophers of his time, Pythagoras had a distinct mysticism to himself, his communities,
and his philosophy. Following elaborate codes of conduct and induction into mysteries this
philosophical following had distinctly religious tones and aspects to it, which other philosophers
pushed back against.
The metaphysical foundation of Pythagoreanism was comprised of various fundamental
components. These components were Metempsychosis, mysticism and numerology. The
Metempsychosis was that all souls were immortal, indestructible and lead to forms of reincarnation
after death, that the soul was transferred to a new body. Pythagoras himself was allegedly claimed to be
a reincarnation of Aithalides (a son of Hermes) by Pherekydes for his mental aptitude and curiosity.
The Mysticism of the Pythagorean metaphysics was expressed in alleged participation in rituals such as
divination or prophecy, likely forms of prediction caused as byproduct from the upcoming
understanding on Numerology. Numerology is most likely the most famous aspect of Pythagoras and
Pythagoreanism, along with the commonly dubbed Pythagorean Theorem (Though the theorem
preceded Pythagoras and was likely acquired by him via studies from the Middle East and North
Africa). Not unlike contemporary understandings of celestial mechanics, astronomy and physics,
Pythagoras held that all of reality was bound by mathematical functions. This was a strict causal
relationship that could be observed and predicted, relating back to the accusations of divination and
prophecy. Pythagoras held the Number three to be an ideal, fundamental number. This came from a
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
16
combination of a monad (1), representing the origin of existence, and the dyad (2), representing
physical existence and matter) combined. As such he and his followers had a great fondness for
triangles, the tetractys (a large triangle with 10 dots within separating it into various other triangles)
became a sacred geometric symbol for the Pythagoreans.
The Pythagorean ethics was greatly founded on their understanding of nature, especially the
aforementioned Metempsychosis. With the understanding of every physical body in reality possibly (if
not definitely) containing a soul just like theirs the Pythagoreans and Pythagoras lived a Vegetarian
lifestyle with one odd addition: they were forbidden from eating beans. This was due to a combination
of older Greek mysticism and Pythagoras' own investigations. Pythagoras believed that beans and
humanity shared a similar origin, something confirmed in his eyes upon watching a bean sprout.
Diagramming both a sprouting bean and a human fetus he saw that there was a distinct similarity, and
as such with the kinship between beans and humanity there would be the added possibility of beans
being soul-bearing. Along with that the Pythagoreans engaged in a form of elitism, keeping distant
from the common lifestyles of those around them, and engaged information from without their
community suspiciously. There were tests, training, initiations and other rituals that would be
undertaken by the Pythagoreans. Despite the many restrictions presented, there are records to show a
sexually egalitarian tradition, which would make sense considering their Metempsychosis beliefs. In
addition there was a focus on attaining purity as to allow the Pythagoreans to better live and attain
higher states of awareness of reality.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
17
Sophists
The last of these Pre-Socratic groups to be mentioned are the Sophists. While this group is more
known for their condemnation and reciprocated contempt of Socrates, they did serve an important role
in Ancient Greece. Though not holding a set of philosophical beliefs and edicts that bound them all to
one another, what did hold the group together was a common appreciation of observed and witnessed
knowledge, an appreciation of rhetoric and its importance, and their status as professional educators,
often taking up the role of tutor to the various wealthy families of Ancient Greece. While having these
common points each were subjective, giving their own interpretations, without the regulation of a
common school and discussion to ensure a higher level of objectivity. Their duty was to assist in
raising the children, particularly the male children, of the wealthy families of Greece to continue in
their success. Socrates famously gained their ire by approaching them on his search for wisdom and
knowledge only to find them to be contradictory, empty, and false. One of the most well known of the
Sophists was Protagoras of Abdera, being one of Sophists identified by Plato, and agitating Plato
further with the statement “Man is the measure of all things” (Pastor, C., n.d., Protagoras (fl. 5th c.
B.C.E.)) . This focus on subjectivity would have also prevented the Sophists from operating more
closely to one another, not having a common universal understanding to work upon.
Socratic Philosophy
Socrates, the legendary Gadfly of Athens, is likely the most well known philosopher to have
never written anything. Taking to his philosophical mission after being proclaimed by an oracle as the
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
18
wisest man he initially went to discover what the god and oracle meant by calling him the wisest man.
In this venture he became well known in Athens, gathered a significant following, inspired a great
number of others to the pursue philosophy. After his death his life was immortalized in the writings of
his student, Plato, to be under the title of “Platonism” despite the most famous and influential texts
focused squarely on Socrates.
When it comes to metaphysics, Socrates has a much greater interest in the non-physical rather
than the physical, the most important aspect of which being the human soul. Soul in this case being the
manifestation of consciousness that animates beings and allows them to live and direct themselves, and
not solely reliant to humans.
... The choice of the souls was in most cases based on their experience of
a previous life. There he saw the soul which had once been Orpheus
choosing the life of a swan out of enmity to the race of women, hating to
be born of a woman because they had been his murderers; he beheld the
soul of Thamyras choosing the life of a nightingale; birds, on the other
hand, like the swan and other musicians, wanting to be men. The soul
which obtained the twentieth lot chose the life of a lion, and this was the
soul of Ajax the son of Telamon, who wanted not be a man, remembering
the injustice which was done him in the judgment about the arms. The
next was Agamemnon, who took the life of a eagle, because, like Ajax, he
hated human nature by reason of his sufferings.” (Plato, 2008, p. 276)
It would seem that all other beliefs that Socrates held was derived from this interest with the soul,
understanding and improving it, living in best accordance as to nurture it. From that comes his great
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
19
love of wisdom. As part of this metaphysical stance he came to a number of conclusions. From
examining the world empirically and reflecting upon what he discovered he came to various
conclusions, including the immortality of the soul, its reincarnation over the course of history, the
notion of an ultimate reality in which knowledge is retrieved (the realm of forms), and the existence of
extraphysical realms. In addition to this he had a notion of, or at the very least claimed to have a notion
of, deities. His philosophical quest was inspired by a question given to an oracle who then identified
Socrates as the wisest of men, and he makes continual references to serving ‘the god’ by having a love
of wisdom and seeking wisdom.
Regarding epistemology, Socrates as notoriously skeptical, though not necessarily to the same
level that other epistemologists may take their field. Rather than being in doubt about any and all
knowledge whatsoever he had doubt as to what commonly passed of as wisdom or knowledge in
society. His continual efforts to be as a self-described ‘Gadfly’ to the Athenian people is what lead him
to his eventual death by Hemlock. He spent his time traveling and seeking out those who claim to be
intelligent and wise before summarily dissecting them and everything they claim to know through a
thorough and merciless series of inquiries. This earned him a reputation in Athens which lead him to be
both greatly loved and hated. This reputation was also the cause of a number of his dialogues, many
were held because those who either admired him or resisted him asked him to speak about his insights
on various topics.
While his epistemological stance was greatly skeptical, though not necessarily to the high
degree that other philosophical skeptics have taken it to, it was this skepticism that earned him an
infamous reputation. Through his persistent questioning he came to find that those who had claims to
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
20
knowledge, upon a bit of prodding, were faulty for one reason or another. This earned him the infamy
of allegedly not having beliefs or stances of his own, but rather that he took it to pick apart the
ideologies of others. This wasn't true, as he did propose many stances, though it is difficult to parse
what he actually held to be true versus what he put forward experimentally or for provocative purposes.
His skepticism was more in line with Cynicism rather than sheer contemporary skepticism, meaning
that he was more interested in reflecting upon what society puts forwards as true rather than worrying
about proofs to justify the trusting of phenomenological perception or worrying about a variety of
psychology or physics in regards to perceiving reality. When it comes to rationalism and empiricism he
tends towards the rationalistic argument, having a stated belief about the immortality of the soul and
that in life it's a matter of remembering rather than truly learning.
... [Socrates:] For if the living spring from any other things, and they too
die, must not all things at last be swallowed up in death? ...
[Cebes:] and we have not been deluded in making these admissions; but I
am confident that there truly is such a thing as living again, and that the
living spring from the dead, and that the souls of the dead are in
existence…
Your favorite doctrine, Socrates, that knowledge is simply recollection,
if true, also necessarily implies a previous time in which we have learned
that which we now recollect. But this would be impossible unless our soul
had been in some place before existing in the form of man; here then is
another proof of the soul's immortality.” (Plato, Phaedo)
Ethics is where Socrates shines the most. His investigations regarding justice, most prominently
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
21
in The Republic, are some of the greatest aspects of his work. In the Republic it was the investigation
upon justice that lead to the talk of political philosophy in the first place
But in reality justice was such as we were describing, being concerned
however, not with the outward man, but with the inward, which is the true
self and concernment of man: for the just man does not permit the several
elements within him to interfere with one another, or any of them to do the
work of others, - he sets in order his own inner life, and is his own master
and his own law, and at peace with himself; and when he has bound
together the three principles within him, … and is no longer many, but has
become one entirely temperate and perfectly adjusted nature, then he
proceeds to act, if he has to act … always thinking and calling that which
preserve and cooperates with this harmonious condition, just and good
action, and the knowledge which presides over it, wisdom, and that which
at any time impairs this condition, he shall call unjust action, and the
opinion which presides over it ignorance.” (Plato, 2008, p.113)
It was in trying to understand the human soul and human psyche that he lead to his tripartite
construction of a perfect city, splitting both the human psyche and city into three parts: the functional
and bodily aspect aimed towards gathering resources and tending to itself, the spirited and honor aspect
aimed towards protection and defense, and the wise aspect aimed towards reflection, discovery,
wisdom and philosophy. It is from this that the notion of Philosopher-King was devised, being that
only the true lovers of wisdom would be able to follow appreciate justice so thoroughly and be able to
properly discover the good.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
22
It was here he established that justice, and by the extent goodness, is for everyone to perform
the functions they ought to do. Though it is the case that later on Socrates seems to either rescind on
this argument or neglect it. After a lengthy description of a perceived afterlife he states that
“And thus, Glaucon, the tale has been saved and has not perished, and
will save us if we are obedient to the word spoken; and we shall pass
safely over the river of Forgetfulness and our soul will not be defiled.
Wherefore my counsel, that we hold fast ever to the heavenly way and
follow after the virtue always, considering that the soul is immortal and
able to endure every sort of good and every sort of evil. Thus shall we live
dear to one another and to the gods, both while remaining here and when,
like conquerors in in the games who go round to gather gifts, we receive
our reward. And it shall be well with us both in this life and in the
pilgrimage of a thousand years which we have been describing.” (Plato,
2008, p.277) .
This is where he seems to fall most closely to doctrinal or religious argumentation, that the treat of
punishment alone is to encourage others to be good, along with additional rewards of the ability to pick
the life they would be reincarnated to and the threat of never being reincarnated if they are evil enough.
Uniquely, Socrates seems to put forward rather egalitarian ideas forward, particularly in The
Republic. The reach of this is across all souls, not just humans, which makes it even more astonishing
(if he really did believe what he was putting forward). In multiple accounts in the Republic he
encouraged women to be given similar, if not the same, tasks as men.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
23
“Are dogs divided into hes and shes, or do they both share equally in
hunting and in keeping watch and in the other duties of dogs? Or do we
entrust to the males the entire and exclusive care of the flocks, while we
leave the females at home, under the idea that the bearing and suckling of
their puppies is enough labor for them?
No, he said, they share alike; the only difference between them is that the
male are stronger and the females are weaker.
… If women are to have the same duties as men, they must have the same
nurture and education?
Yes.”(Plato, 2008, p.118)
While he does refer to women as 'weaker', it is a physical reference, and not that of their ability
as a thinking entity, but also due to their additional task of giving birth. While this may seem as a
discrepancy the women of the Socratic republic are given freedoms the likes of which were extremely
unusual at the time, even fair say in picking who their partner was, ability to be members of the
military and ruling classes. If that wasn't far enough egalitarianism towards the end of the republic in
describing the reincarnation of the soul he makes mention of a swan taking the life of a human, and
humans taking the lives of animals. In here it would seem that Socrates equalizes souls across the
species barrier, though to what extent is not known. By allowing animals and humans to become one
another and act interchangeably it would seem to have massive implications for moral and ethical
theory, though this isn't delved into more deeply. In addition there doesn't seem to be any mention of
Socrates delving more deeply into animal ethics or even more surface level commitments such as
vegetarianism,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
24
To be held as representative of this philosophy will be both Socrates and Plato insofar as the
Platonic representation of Socrates will be used. This is necessary due to the fact that Socrates never
wrote anything of his own but Plato was less inclined to live in the manner that Socrates put forward.
Socrates went as far as he could to embody his philosophy, living meagerly, having no funds (as he
says multiple times in his Apology), and seeking to both examine and encourage examination.
Additionally, for the rest of this piece the philosophy of Socrates will be spoken of in tandem with
Platonism.
Platonism
Socrates' most famous student and chronicler would undoubtedly be Plato. While his works are
known there is difficult between distinguishing his philosophies from that of his teacher, and there is
debate in academia as to how much the depiction of Socrates was skewed for Plato's intentions. If the
portrayal is accurate it can be said that Plato did carry on his master's work, though not embodying it in
deed as Socrates did.
Plato did not take upon the ethics of the Socratic life. He did not walk around consistently
barefoot and verbally accost passersby about everything they thought they knew, nor was that ever
explicitly a goal of his. His interests were more towards documenting, spreading, and institutionalizing
the practice of philosophy via establishing the Academy and taking up the profession of teaching. He'd
lecture and encourage debate rather than going far and wide as his mentor did.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
25
Aristotelian/Peripateticism
Aristotle is likely Plato's most famous student. An extremely prolific author, there's hardly a
known field he he excludes from her purview. He, unlike Plato, did not continue the tradition of his
mentor and instead split off to start his own school of thought. Aristotle went to found the Peripatetic
school, the first Aristotelian school, within the Lyceum.
When it came to physics and metaphysics, Aristotle was primarily materialistic, though with a
concept and understanding of extra-physicality. Unlike Socrates before him it seemed there was a
greater tendency towards inequality when it came to souls. For Socrates what was needed for a soul to
be good was simply to have a philosophical, a wisdom-loving, inclination or nature. To Aristotle there
were inherent differing qualities of souls that ought to be respected and reinforced socially as to allow
for function and cohesion. He had an understanding of three categories of substance in the world,
things that were constantly in motion, things that were constantly still, and things that could alternate
between motion and stillness. This leads to his theory on divinity, being the intelligence that began
movement but was not moved themselves, which was later expanded upon by St. Thomas Aquinas.
When it came to epistemology, Aristotle was heavily empirical. It was in part thanks to his
efforts in epistemology, physics and metaphysics that laid a groundwork for future natural philosophy
and sciences. His treatises were as such a byproduct of heavy empirical study, examining the functions
of the world around him, documenting it and theorizing as to the basis of it in order to allow for a
cohesive philosophy. As a student in the Socratic tradition he was not without a skeptical inclination
and as such spent some time in his treatises attempting to disprove the theories of his predecessors, in
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
26
particular Plato.
When it came to ethics, Aristotle was a virtue moralist and helped solidify virtue ethics. To
Aristotle the virtues were means in which the soul operated, different qualities of action and
determining what action to take. What mattered was seeking to bring about proper balance to the
pursuit of each virtue, the most important virtues of which being courage, justice, prudence and
temperance. When one indulges in a virtue too much or too little there is an imbalance which then leads
to immoral conduct.
It is a middle state between two faulty ones, in the way of excess on one
side and of defect on the other: and it is so moreover, because the faulty
states on one side fall short of, and those on the other exceed, what is
right, both in the case of the feelings and the actions; but Virtue finds, and
when found adopts, the mean. And so, viewing it in respect of its essence
and definition, Virtue is a mean state; but in reference to the chief good
and to excellence it is the highest state possible.” (Aristotle, 2003)
Valor, for example, was the virtuous medium between cowardice (the complete fear of endangerment
of self), and recklessness (the senseless disregard of endangerment of self). All other proper modes of
operation or conduct would find themselves in this same virtuous mean between two vices. What was
important to Aristotle was allowing for a practical, living morality that both people and states could
abide by for proper conduct.
In addition to these virtue ethics Aristotle had an understanding of peoples places in society. As
earlier mentioned he lacked the general egalitarian inclination that Socrates began and falls more
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
27
rigidly into authoritarianism and stratification. Aristotle's view of women is an inherent difference
between them and men, and an inherent inferiority and belonging to first their families and then their
husband. Their contentedness and happiness is given merit of importance insofar as it allows for a
peaceful and ordered society to be allowed to exist, attributing revolution as primarily inspired by the
discontent of women.
"[T]he male, unless constituted in some respect contrary to nature, is by
nature more expert at leading than the female, and the elder and complete
than the younger and incomplete" …
"[T]he relation of male to female is by nature a relation of superior to
inferior and ruler to ruled" …
"The slave is wholly lacking the deliberative element; the female has it but
it lacks authority; the child has it but it is incomplete"” (Clayton, E., n.d.,
Aristotle: Politics )
Due to the extensive amounts of work created by Aristotle and the fact that he founded the
school himself, Aristotle is the greatest representative possible of both early Aristotelianism and the
Peripatetic school in Ancient Greece. There were a number of Scholarchs, leaders of the Peripatetic
school, that would serve as representatives for later Aristotelian philosophy.
Eudaimonic or Socratic Schools
Following the life of Socrates arose a group of philosophical schools, each emphasizing
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
28
different parts of his philosophy. The schools that arose were Stoicism, Cynicism, Epicureanism and
Skepticism. Many of these schools share similar factors such as tendencies towards asceticism and
simple living, tendencies towards having strong ethical and virtuous inclinations, tendencies towards
having philosophical investigations towards truth, and the necessity of living a ‘reflected life’. Many
factors varied greatly within these schools, such as the degree in which these schools followed
Socrates' philosophies, their popularity or prominence, and the ways in which they expressed their
philosophy.
Platonism is not contained within this group due to the difficulty in discerning it from Socratic
philosophy itself, considering it was Plato who documented the near entirety of Socrates' work. These
schools in consequence sprung from Plato's works and the establishment of the Academy, making
Socrates' works more widespread and known, and must easier to study rather than following Socrates
in his endless journey, hoping he finds someone to interrogate or someone to goad him into discourse.
Eudaimonic arises from the Greek word Eudaimonia, εὐδαιμονία, meaning “happiness and welfare”
and is the pursuit of a good, moral life. It is derived from the words “eu”, meaning good, and “daimon”,
meaning spirit. The Eudaimonic philosophies of Ancient Greece are the Cynics, the Stoics, the
Epicureans, the Academic Skeptics, the Pyrrhonian Skeptics and the Cyrenaics.
Cynicism
The Eudaimonic school of Cynicism was very similar to that of Stoicism in many ways,
particularly in the ascetic lifestyle that was emphasized. A primary concern of their philosophy is to
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
29
live in accordance with the “principles of nature”, engage in counterculture activities such as decrying
the traditional values of the people that they live around, and use caustic treatment of their
contemporaries in order to prod them into improving themselves and taking up the task of seeking a
virtuous life.
The main interest of the Cynics was that of ethics, to the point where they heavily neglected
natural philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology, logic, and aesthetics. The focal point of their
philosophy was the ethical and virtuous life that would be brought forth by living an austere life of
poverty and shamelessness. These philosophers sought to attain happiness and eudaimonia through
embodying virtues necessary for “human excellence”. These virtues include self-sufficiency,
shamelessness, candidness, “manliness”, and love of wisdom. While not being a philosophy with an
explicit metaphysical stance or particular religious alignment across all its followers there is sometimes
references to gods by Cynics as to justify what they consider to be virtues.
One common trait expressed is a reverence of deification of nature, manifesting in an interest in
living in accordance to principles of nature, two of the greatest examples of this is their asceticism and
their notion of self-sufficiency. Self-sufficiency involves both the cynic having minimal needs to be
fulfilled and them being able to satisfy as many of their needs as possible without relying on others. In
spite of this the main occupation of Cynics would be begging, though not humbly pleading for alms.
Much like Socrates, who believed himself to be a “gadfly” to encourage his people towards Philosophy
the Cynics saw themselves in a similar position, having to adopt virtuous living to such an extreme
degree as to rely upon others as to encourage others to adopt cynical virtues. It could be said that the
Cynics, maybe more than any other philosophical tradition, embodied the lifestyle that Socrates was
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
30
advocating for. Additionally there is a belief that those who live in great accordance with nature,
seeming to mean living in a way that is most akin to how humans would have lived without the
interference of the many false beliefs that people hold.
Along with a reverence of nature there is a focus on the human 'soul' and its good as the goal of
this philosophy. Due to a limited metaphysical explanation it is not solidified if by soul they are
referring to a physical or extraphysical manifestation of the human mind. Considering they are within
the Socratic tradition and their repeated reference to piety and deities
The Cynics gained notoriety from their 'biting' manner of speech and the aggression they have
towards human civilization. It is partially from this that they earned their title of Cynic, meaning
'Doglike'.
95 The people of Athens called Diogenes ‘the Dog’ because he made the
ground his bed and would spend the night in the streets in front of doors;
but Diogenes liked this nickname because he saw that it was appropriate
to the way in which he conducted himself. For he knew, as Plato recounts
about the nature of dogs, that it is their way to love those whom they know
and to fawn on them, whilst they growl at those whom they do not know,
and that they distinguish enemies from friends, not because they have any
knowledge of good and evil, but because they either know people or do
not know them. The philosopher must be of such a nature that he does not
hate someone because that person does not give him anything, but rather
that he should regard as a friend anyone whom he sees to be in possession
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
31
of virtue, and recognize someone as alien to him in so far as he sees
badness in him.” (Hard, R., 2012, p.26)
Despite the manner of speech that the Cynics adopted being caustic, insulting and belittling
others, they hold that all this was necessary. Adopting an example given by Socrates, that Doctors
wield bitter medicine to heal bodies, not sweet and pleasurable medicine, they believed that it would
require bitterness to encourage others to heal their souls and understanding. They wanted to prevent
their peers from living in a manner that would ultimately be harmful to them.
In pursuit of these virtues Diogenes of Sinope is a suitable representative and one of the most
notorious Cynics in all of history. Unfortunately with the tenants of Cynicism including asceticism and
the degree to which Diogenes was ascetic there's no evidence that that he ever wrote down any of his
works. Like Socrates, Diogenes rather embodied his philosophy, living it and pursuing it in his life
while only being documented by others. He lived so simply that he was recorded only possessing 4
objects for extended periods of time: a storage jar (where he slept), a lantern, a cloak, and a cup. This
limited inventory did not last, for he famously discarded his cup upon seeing a child drinking by
cupping their hands. Living off a simple diet of whatever he could get from begging (with the
possibility of denying more lavish dishes for more simple ones, though there are contradictory reports),
leaving behind shame and social inhibition, and seeking eudaimonia through virtue Diogenes was
emblematic of what it is to embody the cynical philosophies.
Diogenes of Sinope is the chosen representative of the Cynical philosophy, despite not being the
first or founder of it. That title would go to his mentor Antisthenes, a student of Socrates. While
Antisthenes may be the first of the school, Diogenes embodied its philosophy to the fullest and became
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
32
the standard which all other Cynics were to compare their life to. His respect for nature, disrespect for
societal values, sarcastic and satirical nature, abrasive demeanor and asceticism makes him the ideal
cynical philosopher.
Stoicism
Likely the most prominent and influential of the Eudaimonic schools, with strong ethical and
lifestyle values that had far reaching impact ideologically. The central ethical focus of their philosophy
is a form of emotional disassociation from living, that which leads one to satisfaction. This is not at all
a unique ideology, the training towards emotional stillness and asceticism being well established in
Asia at the time by the likes of Buddhism, and the Stoics had exposure and were influenced by the
Indian and Middle-Eastern Gymnosophists who already practiced a similarly ascetic lifestyle.
Their metaphysics were not necessarily cohesive across the ideology, but much like Socrates
before them they had great investment in the power and ability of the human mind and soul. In that way
there is an increased effort and urgency to disassociate the mind/soul and the body. Their metaphysical
understanding served more as an underlying structure as to help their ethical understanding. Similar to
the Cynics, the Stoics had a deep reverence for nature and often conflated divinity with the universe
and nature, and as such the pursuit of a divine or right way of living would live in accordance with
natural principles. Zeno of Citium, much like the Pre-Socratics, theorized on the elemental beginnings
of the universe. He believed in the theory that the universe began with fire that eventually settled into
air, then water, then in most stillness became earth and from this all the diversity of the universe came.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
33
It was in the initial flame that movement came from, and that the soul is akin to a flame, a movement
that keeps what is normally still moving. This reflects the stillness of the body in death, that the soul
and agitating flame has left it. One aspect of Greek Stoic metaphysics was a more physicalist
understanding of reality.
Stoics thought that everything real, that is, everything that exists, is
corporeal―including God and soul. They also recognized a category of
incorporeals, which included things like the void, time, and the
“sayables” (meanings, which played an important role in Stoic Logic).”
(Pigliucci, M., n.d., Stoicism)
The ethics of the Stoics was what governed the existence and importance of their ideology.
What was good to the Stoics was Eudaimonia, a good life, and it is what they pursued. The importance
was placed on emotional detachment from living in order to allow them to live more peacefully and
pursue the more logical and less destructive desires of the mind. The body was not to be neglected, but
not to be indulged, since it was a necessary vessel for the soul in its temporal physical existence. The
importance of rejecting most emotion comes from the belief that virtue is a byproduct of reason, and as
such vice is that absence and rejection of reason. The resulting emotions allowed would be will,
caution, and joy, and the avoidance of desire, fear, pleasure and pain. To the Stoics logic and ethics
were inseparably connected since it was from reason and logic that goodness arose. It is this logical
approach to emotion from which ‘Apatheia’, or Apathy, became an integral concept within their
philosophy. “apatheia: freedom from passion, a constituent of the eudaimôn life” (Pigliucci, M., n.d.,
Stoicism)
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
34
The Stoic ethics arose from the Stoic approach to logic and reason in everyday life. It was all
about understanding what was in their control, and not engaging in fruitless, useless, and foolish
pursuits to control the uncontrollable. It is why they generally seem to disconnect from the rest of the
world emotionally, because it is beyond their influence to control, and as such there is no reason or
point in stressing or fretting over what is beyond their scope. Their home was destroyed in a storm?
That was the will of the gods, and if they did not neglect their virtues then they still left the situation
optimally. Has the government treated you unfairly? That is a misstep on their part in the path of virtue,
and while unfortunate it should not cause disquiet within you. It is from this understanding where
peace, tranquility and some form of happiness, contentedness or Eudaimonia is found.
For the Stoics, then, the “passions” are not automatic, instinctive
reactions that we cannot avoid experiencing. Instead, they are the result
of a judgment, giving “assent” to an “impression.” So even when you
read a familiar word like “fear,” don’t think of the fight-or-flight
response that is indeed unavoidable when we are suddenly presented with
a possible danger. What the Stoics meant by “fear” was what comes after
that: your considered opinion about what caused said instinctive reaction.
The Stoics realized that we have automatic responses that are not under
our control, and that is why they focused on what is under our control: the
judgment rendered on the likely causes of our instinctive reactions, a
judgment rendered by what Marcus Aurelius called the ruling faculty (in
modern cognitive science terminology: the executive function of the
brain).” (Pigliucci, M., n.d., Stoicism)
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
35
In a way the Stoics could have been a reaction Cynics. Having the same focus on asceticism
while being less aggressive, more relaxed and contemplative and with the allowance of a few more
commodities, it was a more tenable lifestyle than the Cynics provided. A calm, collected, reasonable
approach to living was more easily achieved to the masses than to be impoverished, exposed to the
elements on the streets accosting passersby and insulting them. This is due to the fact that Zeno of
Citium was trained under various Socratic philosophies, from the Socratic dialogues, to the Cynics
under Crates of Thebes, along with Academic Skeptic influence.
In selecting a proper representative of the Greek school of Stoicism there is no one better to turn
to in Greece than Zeno of Citium. While very little is left of his works the importance of him founding
the school in Athens after being inspired by Plato cannot be overstated. While others, such as
Chyrsippus, can be held as being influential or even revolutionary in regards to the Stoic school in
Greece, Zeno is the soil from which is sprouted from and is key in the formation of the Stoic ideology.
Epicureanism
Epicureanism is a philosophical school founded by Epicurus with the ethical focus on pleasure.
The pursuit of pleasure would not be found in expected indulgence of drugs, luxury, food, and other
debauchery, but instead with a disciplined, moderated and controlled approach to life. The
representative for this philosophy will be its founder, most influential member, and most prolific writer
regarding Epicureanism in ancient Greece.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
36
Metaphysically the approach of Epicureanism had more of a physicalist bent, being Atomists,
Atomism entails that reality is both physical and comprised of physical components that eventually
reach a point of no division (in contrast to Corpuscularianism). This may be what lends the Epicureans
to be more concerned with the body than the other schools, having it be of increased significance that
may be seen as on-par with that of the body. His understandings of metaphysics could be found as
contentious for his time. When discussing death and the natural worry that most people have towards
its inevitable approach Epicurus has “The Principal Doctrines” regarding death.
II Death is nothing to us. For what has been dissolved has no sense-
experience and what has no sense-experience is nothing to us.”(Brennan,
Stainton, p.167)
In this way Epicurus seems to put forward a senselessness to death, which is in contrast to the
Socratic position of the activity of the soul post mortem. The Epicurean position would then follow that
life is the finite time in which existence is possible, that in death there is annulment and destruction of
the soul and consciousness. In addition to the “tetrapharmakos” as documented by Lucretius “‘God
holds no fears, death no worries. Good is easily attainable, evil easily endurable.'” (Simpson, D., n.d.,
Lucretius (c. 99―c. 55 B.C.E.)) it would seem inevitable that accusations of atheism would be likely
for Epicurus as he presents a philosophy where one needn't take into account extraphysicality,
spiritualism or deities. The mention of spirit is made, though the contemporary distinction of spirit isn't
necessarily there. The more contemporary notion of the spirit being a non-physical aspect of a human
(or other conscious entity) that can exist separate of the body, can work in conjunction with the mind,
and allows for existence beyond death
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
37
Epistemologically the Epicureans are empiricists. They are of the belief that the primary way to
get knowledge regarding the universe is through witnessing phenomena and having sensation, having a
belief that the senses are without fault “... According to Epicurus: They cannot be wrong (LS 16A).
Your senses are infallible guides to the way that the external world is interacting with your body.”
(Adamson, 2015, p. 24) . While this fails to take into account some of the psychological phenomena
and tendencies we are aware of today it does allow for a decent basis for an attempt at a systemic
approach to understanding reality. Appreciating empirical observation is not the end of their
epistemology since they do allow for deduction and reasoning.
Their ethics were centered around the notion of maximizing pleasure, but in an ultimate sense.
By 'ultimate sense', what is meant is that the seeking of pleasure and gratification is not a pursuit
concerned with immediate dividends. Their acquisition of pleasure takes into account the entirety of the
subject's life, insofar as can be predicted, and seeks to maximize it across the lifetime. Unlike sheer
indulgence and hedonism there is the necessity of moderation. Additionally, there is the necessity of
taking into consideration the pleasures of the mind. In the Letter to Menoeceus, Epicurus puts forward
132 For it is not drinking bouts and continuous partying wand enjoying
boys and women, or consuming fish and other dainties of an extravagant
table, which produce the pleasant life, but sober calculation which
searches out the reasons for every choice and avoidance and drives out
the opinions which are the source of the greatest turmoil for men's souls”
(Brennan, Stainton, p.166)
With these conditions many commonly believed sources of pleasure were abstained from. Drugs,
alcohol, and the pursuit of other delights that damage the body are discouraged for the future pain. In
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
38
The Principal Doctrines Epicurus claims.
XX The flesh took the limits of pleasure to be unlimited, and [only] an
unlimited time would have provided it. But the intellect, reasoning out the
goal and limit of the flesh and dissolving the fears of eternity, provided us
with the perfect way of life and had no further need of unlimited time. But
it [the intellect] did not flee pleasure, and even when circumstances
caused and exit from life it did not die as though it were lacking any
aspect of the best life.(Brennan, Stainton, p.168)
This is in stark comparison to the Cynics and Stoics, who seek the denial of pleasures, even subtly
speaking ill of them by referring to pleasure as necessary for “the best life”, meaning those who didn't
accept this more holistic approach were lacking the best life.
While sprouting from the philosophical movement caused by Socrates it is almost undoubted
that Socrates would have chastised the pursuit of pleasure that Epicurus held high. This is despite the
similarity in lifestyle that the Epicureans had to many other Eudaimonic schools: living modestly,
engaging in philosophical discourse and reflection, seeking truth and goodness in all things and
encouraging others to do so as well. The interest in pleasure is what keeps this school separate from all
the others, even in utilizing temperance.
... if the nature of justice and injustice be known, then the meaning of
acting unjustly and being unjust, or, again, of acting justly, will also be
perfectly clean? … they are like a disease and health; being in the soul
just what disease and health are in the body? … that which is healthy
causes health, and that which is unhealthy causes disease. … And just
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
39
actions cause justice, and unjust actions cause injustice? … Then virtue is
the health and beauty and well being of the soul, and vice the disease and
weakness and deformity of the same? … And do not good practices lead
to virtue, and evil practices to vice? … Still, our old question of the
comparative advantage of justice has not been answered: which is more
profitable, to be.” (Plato, 2008, p.114)
It could easily be argued that seeking pleasure as the core of the philosophical pursuit of virtue and
goodness, even if moderated, would eliminate it as a proper pursuit . Unfortunately this school started
after the life and death of both Socrates and Plato and as such there were no interactions between the
founders of the ideologies.
Skepticism : Academic
Unlike the other Eudaimonic schools, the Skeptical schools of philosophy were more based in
the epistemology and the methodology of Socrates rather than his ethical stance. In the same way that
Socrates went forth questioning those who claimed to have knowledge the Skeptics went forth to
question everything they could, from firmly established cultural beliefs to newly discovered. This leads
them to have the moniker of being a negative philosophy rather than a positive one, meaning that
instead of putting anything forward (any positive claims) they examine the claims of others and attempt
to disprove them.
None of this is to say that no individual member of the school had their own stances on any
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
40
number of important topics. As individuals it isn't the case that the members of this school were
completely skeptical on all matters to the point of having no beliefs of their own. Instead it was a
unified goal of academic and intellectual excellence that urged them to continually doubt and
undermine all things proposed to them for any fault.
Epistemology and logic is where the skeptics shine. Testing standards of knowledge,
discovering and examining paradoxes, looking over the theories of others, finding and exploiting their
faults. This form of academic rigor would encourage a higher standard of thoroughness and quality in
postulating theories as weak ones would not be able to take ground.
This could easily be considered as one of the more unified of the schools, referring less to a
unified ideology and more of a unified movement and objective in philosophy. There was no unified
understanding of metaphysics, ethics or any other field of philosophy, but there was the necessity to
encourage critical thinking wherever they went. In Ancient Greece what is accredited as the first
Skeptical school is the Pyrrhonian Skeptical school.
Due to the relative simplicity and lack of positive ideology put forward by the Greek Academic
Skeptics a single representative for their philosophy will not be necessary, and instead they will be
approached as a movement.
Skepticism : Pyrrhonian
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
41
The Pyrrhonian school was started by Pyrrho of Elis and later revived in part by the Roman
Sextus Empiricus. While Pyrrho, like Socrates, did not write any of his theories. Instead, his student,
Timon of Phlius, did record some of his doctrine along with satirical poems. One of the most revealing
and influential works in regard to Pyrrho is the ‘Aristocles Passage’ which contains the following
questions.
First, what are things like by nature? second, how should we be disposed
towards things (given our answer to the first question)? and third, what
will be the outcome for those who adopt the disposition recommended in
the answer to the second question?” (Bett, R., 2018)
Pyrrho's answers to the questions are as follows.
As for pragmata ‘matters, questions, topics’, they are all adiaphora ‘un-
differentiated by a logical differentia’ and astathmēta‘unstable,
unbalanced, not measurable’ and anepikrita ‘unjudged, unfixed,
undecidable’. Therefore, neither our sense-perceptions nor our ‘views,
theories, beliefs’ (doxai) tell us the truth or lie [about pragmata]; so we
certainly should not rely on them [to do it]. Rather, we should be
adoxastous ‘without views’, aklineis ‘uninclined [toward this side or
that]’, and akradantous ‘unwavering [in our refusal to choose]’, saying
about every single one that it no more is than it is not or it both is and is
not or it neither is nor is not.”(Pyrrho’s Thought, n.d., p. 23)
Here Pyrrho shows his skepticism and doubt in regards to human attempts at understanding the world.
Firstly to claim that the nature of things is unknowable and indiscernible, to follow it by that we
shouldn't be over reliant on our beliefs and theories, and concluding by saying that we should be
without inclination or views and resisting to be affixed to any single ideology. While it may seem
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
42
paradoxical for someone to so dogmatically appeal to indecision existentialists had long ago
understood the choice in not choosing and that
The Pyrrhonians do fit into the Eudaimonic category more than the Academic skeptics, having a
believed notion of a way of life. In that way they upheld an ethical standard. To the Pyrrhonians the
way to a good life is through relieving the stress caused by the psychological dissonance generated
from the epistemic barrier to knowledge. This dissonance causes stress and discontent, but with the
Pyrrhonian school the way to reach satisfaction would to disassociate and remain unattached to theories
involving the universe. In that way they resembled the Stoics and the Cynics. The Stoics would lessen
and detach from emotions and futile pursuits of pleasure that would hold them back, and the Cynics
would detach from shame and other negative social stigma that caused them this negativity in their
lives.
Since the Pyrrhonians are a fairly cohesive school with an established lifestyle and ethical
understanding to their work Pyrrho of Elis fits in being their representative. The lack of work from him
does make it difficult, but the references to him made by Timon of Phlius and Sextus Empiricus will be
used.
Cyrenaics
The Cyrenaics were a relatively small school founded by Aristippus of Cyrene, a follower of
Socrates. The primary doctrine of the Cyrenaics was the importance in the immediate indulgence of
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
43
pleasure. They express ideological similarities to that of the Epicureans and the Pyrrhonian Skeptics
The were similar to the former by their common sense of pleasure seeking and hedonism, and to the
latter due to their embrace of immediate empiricism and epistemological skepticism. To the Cyrenaics
the goal of life was to experience pleasure in the present moment. Unlike the Epicureans, due to their
highly skeptical nature, there was little use in planning for the future or being overly logical in the
indulgence of some reward that has yet to come. Unlike the Pyrrhonians their skepticism was not used
as a mechanism in order for them to better and more carefully try to understand the world around them
in what little ways they can.
Despite being a Socratic or Eudaimonic school the Cyrenaics express what would seem to be a
very strong rejection of the teachings of Socrates. Instead of focusing on the pursuit of enlightenment
and turning away from the common human focus on pleasure they indulge themselves greatly. While
this did not manifest itself as complete loss of self in debauchery, it did very much go against what
Socrates was proclaiming.
Aristippus' ethics are centered around the question of what the 'end' is;
that is, what goal our actions aim at and what is valuable for its own
sake. Aristippus identified the end as pleasure. This identification of
pleasure as the end makes Aristippus a hedonist. Most of the pleasures
that Aristippus is depicted as pursuing have to do with sensual
gratification, such as sleeping with courtesans and enjoying fine food and
old wines.” (O’Keefe, T., n.d., Aristippus (c. 435―356 B.C.E.))
The epistemology of the Cyrenaic is classical skeptical, that the world outside of oneself is nigh
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
44
unknowable. Rather than turning to rationalism, which is closer to what Socrates and the Platonic
schools took, the Cyrenaics turned towards Empiricism. Considering the main means in which a human
engages with information is by witnessing it empirically, the Cyrenaics felt that the best means in
which to engage and operate in the world is based on said impressions. They also had a recognition of
the subjectivity of empiricism, with people recounting the same stimuli in different ways. One such
example could be found in taste, where illness causes one to taste something different from another.
This allowed them to occupy a epistemological space of empirical subjectivism.
To the Cyrenaics the pivotal thing in life was pleasure and enjoyment in the present moment.
Xenophon, a hostile contemporary of Aristippus', reports that Aristippus
rejected delaying any gratification. Aristippus advocated simply deriving
pleasure from whatever is present, and not producing trouble for oneself
by toiling to obtain things which may bring one pleasure in the future.”
(O’Keefe, T., n.d., Aristippus (c. 435―356 B.C.E.))
This did not mean, necessarily, foolishness and foolhardiness. Instead there was need for some amount
of reflection before engaging in actions, but not in an ultimate or very long term sense. Additionally
there was a vivacious nature to this philosophy, encouraging its members to make the most of their
situations and find themselves victors in circumstances where that may be unlikely. Why did they focus
so much on pleasure? It was due to the natural human tendency towards pleasure seeking, and as such
they fell towards what nature was seemingly communicating with them to do. This was not unlike other
Socratic schools, the Cynics for example had a great investment in the natural virtues of self reliance
and 'manliness'.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
45
The representative of the Cyrenaic school will be Aristippus of Cyrene considering he is held as
the founder of the school and one of its more prolific members.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
46
Ancient Roman Philosophy
The Roman civilizations of the Roman Kingdoms, Roman Republic and then the Roman
Empire are at once different from Ancient Greece while being heavily influenced by them. A
cosmopolitan, expansive state that encompassed most of their known world, bringing together people
of numerous cultures and heritages into a single network across western and southern Europe, North
Africa, and the Middle-East. In comparison to the diversity found in the Roman civilization, the Greek
city-states were fairly homogeneous with many similarities (linguistically, culturally, historically, etc.)
that generally stood divided until an outside force brought them together.
The influences on Roman philosophy are many, but some of the most potent influence came
from Ancient Greece. This cultural appropriation is reflected in not only the adoption of a large amount
of Hellenic mythology, theology, and religion but also the philosophy of Ancient Greece. Along with
Ancient Greece, Rome was exposed to all the cultures around the Mediterranean sea and beyond, in
turn influencing and being influenced by these peoples and civilizations. Egypt, the various
civilizations of the Middle East and even Eastern philosophy, such as the Gymnosophists, had their
influence seen in Rome as well.
Eclecticism
With the rise of the pragmatic and cosmopolitan Roman civilizations Eclecticism may seem
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
47
almost inevitable. Instead of being a singular cohesive philosophy it inhabits a similar position that
academic skepticism, that they have a greater vested interest in holding a philosophical mechanism
rather than a singular philosophy. Eclecticism is not a title isolated to philosophy, but is rather
something applicable to any pursuit available. Eclecticism refers to a style in which there is no single,
cohesive style that is adapted but rather fragments from multiple styles are brought together. In
Philosophy this can be expressed by adopting various different philosophical stances even when they
aren't necessarily endemic of one another or even aren't cohesive, compartmentalizing these from one
another in order to prevent excessive conflict. The method in which choosing these different
ideological principles isn't universal, altering from person to person to person due to preference. In
spite of that there is a general tendency towards going towards what appeals to the subject, be it from
perceived truth, goodness, or practicality. In that last merit it would resemble pragmatism.
Its existence is not surprising in the Roman civilization due to the aforementioned cosmopolitan
quality it possesses. With access to so many different philosophies and cultures within the Roman
civilization there is great ability for its citizens to parse through them, adopting whatever theories
suited their causes and cherry-picking around all that which may refute them. Thankfully for these
Eclecticist philosophers they had a great wealth of intellectual tradition within their reach from not only
Greece but also from the Middle-East.
The representative of Eclecticism will be Cicero, considered one of the most prominent
Eclecticism philosophers though his actual contribution to philosophy may be limited. He is known
mostly from his translation of Greek pieces into Latin and his work as a politician in the Roman
Republic, both of which are tied to his study of philosophy. “Cicero chose a career in the law. To
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
48
prepare for this career, he studied jurisprudence, rhetoric, and philosophy.”(Clayton, E., n.d., Cicero
(106―43 B.C.E.)). Considering the close relation to moral theory, rhetoric, oration and the study of
history it proved prudent for Cicero to take up this study in order to excel.
Neopythagoreanism
The teachings of Pythagoras persisted after the rise of the Socratic philosophies, retaining much
of its cult-like and superstitious qualities. It held a focus on the divinity and the ontological significance
of numbers and with great studies into mathematics and what could be discovered there.
Philostratus' voluminous Life of Apollonius explains that the sage of
Tyana was a teacher of asceticism whose personal knowledge featured
not only an understanding of mathematics and philosophy but also direct
revelations from the gods.” (Apollonius of Tyana (n.d.))
While Philostratus himself is considered a Sophist, he was trained by Apollonius of Tyana, one of the
most influential Neopythagoreans. Neopythagoreanism, like Pythagoreanism, retained much of its
mystical or ritual qualities, maintaining many of the laws and codes of conduct established by
Pythagoras and holding their founder in great reverence. Due to the destruction or loss of texts over the
many centuries since their prominence some of the major details of their beliefs have been documented
by others.
The main differences that arose with Neopythagoreanism came from what would then be
contemporary influences. Unlike the original doctrines and beliefs of Pythagoreanism,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
49
Neopythagoreanism was influenced by the teachings of Socrates and Plato, in particular establishing a
relationship between the Platonic Forms and the metaphysical importance of numbers. Due to
combination of these two theories there was metaphysical understanding of 'the Good' and 'the Monad'
(a term that would be later adopted by modern metaphysical dualist Gottfried Leibniz). The Good and
The Monad were predecessor theories to the Neoplatonic theory of The One. This lead to the tiered
understanding of reality, starting with perfection, as can be seen in the Platonic forms and the
Neoplatonic The One, and descending to deceptive and base complete-anti-perfection, as can be seen in
the Neoplatonic Matter.
The metaphysical understanding of the universe according to Neopythagoreanism is distinctly
theistic. “According to Eudorus, the Pythagoreans posited a single supreme principle, known as the one
and the supreme god, which is the cause of all things” (plato.stanford.edu/entries/pythagoreanism)
The Ethical theory of the Neopythagoreans was, like their metaphysics, a blending of both
Platonism and Pythagoreanism with a combination of a seeking of a good and a perfect mathematical
universal harmony being established. One noticeable facet from the Socratic influence was a greater
emphasis on the ascetic lifestyle, something which is reflected in other Socratic schools such as
Cynicism and Stoicism. The reason being was distinct from their peers, namely that in living
ascetically you would be denying the evils of matter, preventing yourself from being base. The Cynics
engaged in ascetics to optimize their self reliance and ensure their purity of virtue, the Stoics to avoid
raised expectations and unnecessary hardship as a result on dependence on pleasure. This is not to deny
the ascetic nature of Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans, but to re-contextualize the circumstances and
causes. In addition to these beliefs there were sets of more mystical ideology as a byproduct of the
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
50
Pythagorean influence, along with an influence of the Orphic mysteries. In this way this philosophy
seemed to veer closely to becoming a religion, and it could easily be seen as a religion in its own right,
much like Pythagoreanism could have easily been identified as a religion.
The representative of Neopythagoreanism will be Apollonius of Tyana. He is considered crucial
in sustaining the tradition but seeking greater understanding that may not have been found therein the
tradition, expanding it to encompass more. While his works did not survive, he is remembered through
the writings of his student, Philostratus the Sophist.
Middle Platonism
The teaching of Socrates and Plato remained influential many years after the death Plato. Being
such a prolific and prominent pair of philosophers, especially with Plato's tendency towards writing and
his founding of the original Academy, lent him to have a sizable following and preservation of his
documents. The main push forward for Middle Platonism against the Academic Skepticism was the
rejection of knowledge as an impossibility, allowing for a firm positive philosophy to come forward.
This was an affirmation of the life of Socrates, his continuous pursuit of knowledge, attempt to do
good, and to seek the light of reason.
Scholars generally consider the Middle Platonic period to have begun
with the work of Antiochus of Ascalon (d. 68 B.C.), who was responsible
for overhauling the increasingly stifling skepticism of the New Academy.”
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
51
(Moore, E., n.d., Middle Platonism)
Middle Platonism functions as a continuation of Platonic philosophy with additional works and
widening the scope that it tackles, along with bringing the Platonic Academy to a more positivist
stance. The additions brought into Platonism to bring it into Middle Platonism there is the inclusion of
Aristotelian work (from the Peripatetic school), Stoic work, and the influence of Pythagoreanism.
Unlike the original academy and the original Platonism, having more of a focus on the Academic
Skeptical aspect of the teachings of Socrates and Plato, this would be a bit more grounded and
functioning, asserting more strongly a positive philosophy.
The ethical core of Middle Platonism was similar to that of the Platonic philosophy, namely the
pursuit of justice. Justice, in this context, was the operation of things in their intended or best suited
place and in their intended or best suited way. It was proper order and configuration, allowing for better
cohesion and cooperation between peoples and mutual respect in seeking ever higher mental aptitude.
It was the understanding of boundaries and rules. While Socrates' doctrine may be vague, but it works
as a proper structure to which other rules and edicts could be founded, and it was especially crucial to
the understandings of the Neopythagoreans. The influence of the Pythagoreans is unmistakable in the
Middle Platonism.Plutarch understood the highest goal of existence as achieving likeness to god, yet
he had little confidence in the ability of human reason to adequately contemplate and understand
divinity, believing instead in the possibility of divine revelations.” (Moore, E., n.d., Middle Platonism)
The metaphysical and physical study of Middle Platonism continued on in the examination of
the Socratic/Platonic forms in comparison to particulars and the extrapolation of their perfection, as
ideal aspects to which all things physical attempt to emulate. This would act as a groundwork for
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
52
Neopythagoreanism and Neoplatonism in their eventual hierarchy of existence. While many of Plato’s
writings had a focus on ethics, epistemology, and cultural critique, there were also clear asides to talk
about metaphysical understanding of the universe. The Phaedo and The Republic included at length
discussions on the nature of the soul and what death is, for example.
The representative of Middle Platonism will be Plutarch of Chaeronea. His selection is due to
him being one of the most renown Middle Platonists and the number of works he produced, both as a
philosopher and a biographer. “Plutarch was a prolific writer. The so-called Lamprias catalogue, an
ancient library catalogue (preserved mutilated) … lists 227 works, several of them no longer extant
(Russell 1973, 18–19). Plutarch's works divide into philosophical and historical-biographical.
(Karamanolis, G., 2014)
Neoplatonism
Neoplatonism on the other hand has a somewhat Eclectic nature, introducing other philosophies
and even theologies into Platonism such as Neopythagoreanism. Coming as a byproduct of a blending
various philosophical and religious traditions it still holds its identity as a form of Platonism thanks to
its tendency towards the Eudaimonic Schools (most especially skepticism and stoicism) and towards
the spiritual aspects of the teachings of Plato and Socrates. Unlike Middle Platonism, Neoplatonism is a
categorization of philosophers and philosophy made retrospectively rather than something necessarily
recognized during its time in Rome.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
53
The Representative of Neoplatonism will be Plotinus, being both one of its most prolific and
earliest philosophers, often considered to be its founder. Neoplatonism, in Plotinus' honor is sometimes
referred to as Plotinism. Neoplatonism is not a then-contemporary ascribed title, instead the title was
placed on them during modernity considering the distinct traits this philosophy does no share with its
originating philosophy.
One of the major focuses of Plotinus and Neoplatonism is the pursuit of understanding reality
via metaphysics. Plotinus organized reality in an order starting with The One. “The One is the
absolutely simple first principle of all. It is both ‘self-caused’ and the cause of being for everything else
in the universe.” (Gerson, L, 2018). The description of existence then describes categories of things
descending from The One. The One, along with it being ontologically self-emergent, has qualities such
as being infinite, being goodness and beauty, being orderly, and being the most real and, most
importantly of all, being the most simple. This simplicity is needed in order to explain how more
complex forms arise from it and All other categories of existence descends from The One, all the way
down to “Matter”. Matter is considered to be comparable to an inversion of The One, namely being the
least real (Non-being) and illusory, being evil, ugly, chaotic, and complex. “According to Plotinus,
Matter is to be identified with evil and privation of all form or intelligibility” (Gerson, L, 2018).
All the aspects of The One are integral to both it and all of reality as a consequence, used to
explain both physical and metaphysical processes. The qualities of goodness and beauty are
complementary, as there is the notion of true beauty accompanying true goodness. The qualities of The
One being the most real, most orderly and most simple allow then that all things branched off from it,
diversions from the seemingly perfect design, can explain all the chaotic, illusory and even unreal
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
54
aspects.
Neoplatonic philosophy is a strict form of principle-monism that strives
to understand everything on the basis of a single cause that they
considered divine, and indiscriminately referred to as “the First”, 'The
One', or “the Good”. Since it is reasonable to assume, as the
Neoplatonists did, that any efficient cause is ontologically prior to, and
hence more real, than its effect, then, in the hierarchy of being, the first
principle, whatever it is, cannot be less “real” than the phenomena it is
supposed to explain.”(Wildberg, C., 2016)
In relation to more traditional Platonism, ‘the One’ is essentially the ultimate form from the
Realm of Forms as Socrates and Plato describes it, additionally embodying the position of the Sun in
the Cave Allegory. The Sun, in the Cave Allegory and especially near the end of the republic, serve the
point in analogy as the creation of existence, life and goodness all in one. As such the One embodies all
of these positive things, being the fount from which all good comes from and the further down the
spectrum of existence something is found the more warped from the perfect qualities of the One until it
eventually reaches the lowest rung for Neoplatonists, referred to as ‘Matter’. This metaphysical stance
is not unique, being reflected by a number of religions, and especially in later Christianity (which can
attribute much of its original philosophical and metaphysical development from Neoplatonism), having
a comparative distancing from God being an attribution to imperfection. Earlier philosophies, such as
the Eleatic school and the Pythagoreans, also had a similar approach to metaphysics.
One thing The One does not possess is intellect, that being a quality of other categories and
beings within it, but not to Matter. Intellect is the first step down from The One, being the faculty of
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
55
comprehension of forms. The category being intellect, that which is one increment below The One, is
sometimes referred to as Divine Intellect. It could reasonably be said that intellect is not necessary for
The One and as such, in the necessity for simplicity, it lacks such a trait. The reason intellect is not
necessary for The One is because it simply is being, not the reflection of being.
Aristotelian/Peripateticism
The Peripatetic school did not have the same following that the other Hellenic schools had in
Rome. “The obscurity of Aristotle's works hindered the success of his philosophy among the Romans.”
(Peripatetics, n.d.). Instead, such there was a greater focus on the Peripatetics to preserve the works of
Aristotle. Aristotelian philosophy did make significant impact to Platonic philosophy in the Roman
empire, and thanks to the semi-Eclectic nature of Middle Platonism and Neoplatonism it took part in
the synthesis these philosophies needed to exist.
Long after the life of the its founder, Aristotle, the Peripatetic school continued into the Roman
empire and around the Mediterranean. Considering its foundations in the Platonic Academy, though
acting as a departure in many ways, it would seem natural that the philosophies would alter due to the
mutual exposure, though the core values remain relatively the same. The Peripatetic school continues
its main divergence from Platonism, namely the emphasis on Empiricism and a more Physicalist
understanding of reality versus the more Rationalistic and Idealistic views that Platonism put forward.
It is in much this way that the Peripatetic school was more similar to natural philosophy than other
Socratic or Socratic-descended philosophies.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
56
The metaphysical stance of the peripatetic school was, as indicated above, physicalistic
(subscribing to physicalism). Namely that the foundation of reality was of two components, that of
matter and forms, though not in the standard Socratic or Platonic understanding. Matter acted as a base
substance which all existence is founded from, without qualities but with infinite potential. The
actualization of the potential comes in the notion of the form, the matter gaining shape and properties in
order to properly operate in a physical world. To explain living things there was a theory of soul, an
animating force or energy, that allows for organisms to operate, though on different levels. The soul is
responsible for the faculties of reproduction, nutrition, memory, recollection, reason, and
understanding, and more, though there wasn't a necessarily extraphysical understanding of said 'soul' as
may be ascribed in a more contemporary understanding. These souls were inherent to and inseparable
from the bodies which they operated.
The ethics and social philosophy of the Peripatetic school acted primarily as an understanding
and justification of the politics it bore to witness and, in turn and partially opposition to the Platonic
works, came to support things like sexism and slavery. Another major facet of the ethical philosophy of
Aristotle was the examination of virtue in an analytical and pseudo-scientific way, namely by
organizing it. The various virtues as listed in the Peripatetic school are only considered virtues in
moderation. The virtues are traditionally between two vices, a prime example being bravery or courage
being the moderation between the vices of foolhardiness and cowardice. Another integral factor of
Aristotelian ethics is the recognition of the virtue within others, submitting to the more virtuous and
dominating over the lesser as to ensure their eventual rise to virtue. As as consequence of this there is a
strong sense of social structure and place for the Peripatetic, along with an acute sociological
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
57
perspective of justified elevation or degradation of a person due to their virtue. This fit well within
Rome, a society that believed itself to be heavily meritocratic and accomplish-oriented.
The representative will be Alexander of Aphrodisias, one of the most important figures in
keeping the philosophy alive into the Roman civilization. He did so by writing commentaries to the
writings of Aristotle, keeping alive the examination of Aristotle's' work into this age. This is in
recognition of the work done by Andronicus of Rhodes who worked to compile the collected works of
Aristotle into the Corpus Aristotelicum.
Eudaimonic or Socratic Schools
The Eudaimonic schools did not go into the Roman civilization unaltered. With the popularity
of Greek culture within the Roman world it goes without saying that some of its most influential
philosophical schools found many sympathetic followers awaiting them. The people of Rome and all
the Mediterranean were seemingly seeking for a path to happiness and Eudaimonia, which these
philosophies offered. The philosophies mentioned previously had aspects of blending and rarification
of ideology. Due to a combined effect of the continued efforts of subsequent philosophers building
upon one another in these philosophies and the ever-increasing exposure to other ideologies these
philosophers were exposed to there came reflection in the work.
When the Roman empire conquered Greece the Socratic schools were prosperous, as such making
them prime for transfer and translation into Latin by Roman intellectuals and scholars. In order to
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
58
ensure the preservation of the work it was common to have texts rewritten, one of the major factors
influencing this was the development of new technologies involving the creation and storage of text.
The Eudaimonic Schools of Ancient Rome are the Cynics, Stoics, Epicureans, Academic Skeptics, and
the Pyrrhonian Skeptics.
Cynicism
Cynicism managed to continue into the Roman civilization, though the transition seems to have
spared nothing of their cause. Still deeply ascetic and virtuous, concerned about the self-sufficiency of
people and the shunning of material goods in order to live more closely with nature. This nature also
makes them notoriously difficult to study posthumously considering it is said material goods that are
needed to document these philosophers, though thankfully there is documentation on their activities,
habits, and wisdom. Cynicism was both loved and hated in the Roman world, admired for the honest
and direct virtuous and good life that is lead of deep sacrifice, but similarly complaints regarding its
practitioners. It is with these complaints that we are assured Diogenes' wishes live on.
It could be theorized that maybe in the very same aspect of the philosophy that would lead to
such a lack of documentation would also lead to the relatively stable nature of the philosophy. Similar
to skepticism, Cynicism has a highly negative disposition, but that is due to a very strong core of
positive believes. The virtues of rationality, self-sustaining, freedom, autonomy, and the importance of
education and information (often translated as 'Manliness') keeps the Cynics busy with deconstructing
the foolishness around them. It is this that also keeps them from giving too much speculation regarding
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
59
the nature of reality or really any other philosophy. While the Philosophical exploration of Absurdism
arise in the 20th century in Europe with philosophers such as Albert Camus, it could be argued Cynics
engaged in this examination heartily, much to the discontent of all those very much invested in their
civilization, traditions, rituals, and social structure.
The representative of this philosophy in Rome will be Demonax, teacher to Lucian of Samosata.
His selection was due to him being one of the most famous Cynic Philosophers of that age, but the
difficulties of the earlier Cynics carries on: the biggest one being that he did not leave any writings.
Thankfully his student, Lucian, wrote the Life of Demonax in honor of his mentor to allow future
generations to bear indirect witness to his philosophy and virtue.
Like Diogenes before him, he did not turn away those who were keen to learn philosophy from
the virtuous, he allegedly lived simply. Considering the famous anecdotes of Diogenes of Sinope,
Demonax was often compared to him, and was even asked which philosophers he admired replying "'I
admire them all; Socrates I revere, Diogenes I admire, Aristippus I love.'” (Lucian of Samosata, n.d.,
LIFE OF DEMONAX). Like Diogenes before him he was known for great stubbornness but also for
virtue. Unlike Diogenes, Demonax earned his reputation as a resolver of arguments and a maker of
peace. Like his philosophical ancestors he also bore a sharp and caustic wit in order to strike down the
foolish, illogical and non-virtuous things he saw about him in society. Demonax became rather revered
in his lifetime, seen as sagely and a bringer of much good to the point where people would happily
offer him stay at their home and as much food as he could want. In the end, after allegedly living nearly
a century, he died from self-imposed starvation and Athens deeply mourned losing him.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
60
Stoicism
Of all the Eudaimonic philosophies, Stoicism was one of the most prosperous in the Roman
empire. There is no shortage of evidence regarding this claim, showing the wide number of people that
adopted this philosophy from all strata of life and all levels of society. This was in part thanks to the
universal usefulness of its tenants, the increasing number of stoic groups being established, and the
works made available for all within the Roman expanse. One of the more influential pieces made the
Enchiridion of Epictetus. Its tenants of emotional distance, mastery of self, and acceptance regarding
what life and fortune may offer remain relatively undisturbed. Stoics even assisted in actualizing a deep
desire of Socrates and Plato; the establishment of a proper ‘Philosopher King’ (as mentioned in The
Republic). This Philosopher King was Marcus Aurelius, the 16th emperor of Rome. He upheld stoic
virtues in his life both as an emperor and as an individual. His works, the Meditations, are held as a
landmark in Stoic philosophy despite the fact that Marcus Aurelius never intended for them to be
published, writing them instead as part of his own personal meditation.
Considering the number of possible candidates the one that is selected will be justified. The
Stoic Philosopher that will represent Stoicism will be Lucius Annaeus Seneca, also known as Seneca
the Younger, or just simply as Seneca. The reason for his selection not only the amount of work he
produced but also the distance he carried his philosophy with him, all the way to the grave.
Being accused by then emperor Nero, who Seneca advised and tutored, of conspiring to betray
him he was sentenced to death. Instead of resisting this fate he instead took up the opportunity given to
him to take his own life rather than be executed, to which he did. Slicing the veins in his wrists he had a
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
61
lingering slow death, according to Tacitus (a roman senator and historian). In the words of Seneca
Can you no longer see a road to freedom? It's right in front of you. You need only turn over your
wrists.” (The School of Life, 2014) . It was the life's work of Seneca to adjust his understanding of life
and assisting others in theirs, allowing them to handle the hardships more favorably.
At the core of the Stoic understanding is the realization that life is fraught with events that are
often used as justification or causes of suffering. The realize that these events are only able to
negatively impact people due to the inherent understood attachment or association between the self and
the event. An example of this would be the incarceration of someone. To a family member of said
incarcerated person, it may be a negative experience and as such inspire grief or frustration. To a
citizen of the state it may be seen as positive, that there is one less criminal threatening them and that
they will now be subject to justice via punishment and rehabilitation. To an anarchist or anti-
establishmentarian, they may be frustrated due to the belief that the justice system is corrupt and that
people's freedoms should not be hindered by governmental and social machinations.
To counteract these frustrations the Stoic focuses inwardly and a certain quality in all events:
either the ability to control or have no control over a situation. Using a dispassionate and neutral
approach they examine a situation to see the degree of control they have over it. If they have no
control, then there was no way to avoid said situation, and as such fretting over the inevitable is
illogical. To all things they can control they focus on trying to optimize the outcome or improve their
situation. The Stoics came to the conclusion that all things external to themselves, namely natural
phenomena and the actions of others, are outside of their control. As such the operations of both the
natural world and the social realm are outside their ability to control or regulate. The Stoic recognizes
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
62
that the only domain in which they have control is the self, how they interpret data and how they act.
Following the determination of control, the Stoics realize that often attachment is what leads to
dissatisfaction and suffering. In the Enchiridion it actively encourages feeling unattached to many
things that are commonly held close, such as family members and spouses, and instead encouraging a
loose attachment on large groups since the human psyche does inherently form attachments.
With regard to whatever objects either delight the mind or contribute to
use or are tenderly beloved, remind yourself of what nature they are,
beginning with the merest trifles: if you have a favorite cup, that it is but a
cup of which you are fond of―for thus, if it is broken, you can bear it; if
you embrace your child or your wife, that you embrace a mortal―and
thus, if either of them dies, you can bear it.” (Epictetus, 2014)
Epicureanism
Epicureanism was also popular in Rome. The focus towards pleasure is one that was widely
appreciated in Rome and the establishment of Epicurean-style homes became widespread across the
civilization. While suffering competition from other Hellenic and Greek philosophical schools,
Epicureanism did make an impact on Roman society. Epicureanism was given consideration alongside
other philosophies such as Platonism, Stoicism and the Peripatetic School.
The representative of Epicureanism will be Lucretius, Titus Lucretius Carus. Despite being
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
63
remembered as a poet, he was also a philosopher. Lucretius was one of the most prominent voices in
the way of Epicureanism both in the natural sciences and morally. It is in part thanks to him that
Epicureanism was able to flourish in the Roman civilization, alongside the staunch opposition of the
Stoics.
In his piece De rerum natura (‘On the Nature of Things’) Lucretius advocated for the Atomist
view that Epicureans had been supporting, pushing back against the various pre-Socratic metaphysical
understandings of the universe. The stance continued that the universe was comprised of physical
matter, one that did not align with any of the previously held fundamental elements of Earth, Water,
Air and Fire, and a void that existed between this matter. Lucretius did not mere propose this
unfounded, but gave reasons as to why none of the other elements could sensibly transmute themselves
or appear as the others, claiming that the reasoning for any of them being the base element of reality is
insubstantial. Lucretius postulated that reality was matter and void, matter lacking what he dubbed
'Secondary Qualities' like the other elements other than merely being physical, and void being
necessary for proper rearrangement of this matter in order to be able to have qualities and interact with
one another.
While many of his beliefs did mirror more contemporary and scientific understandings of
reality, namely that physicality in general is comprised, more or less, of base particles in different
modes and void, Lucretius did oppose the notion of a spherical Earth. Lucretius instead advocated for a
universal structure that would be similar to the Socratic one and many others before it, of different
types of material have what may be called different ‘weights’ or ‘density’, the heavier materials sinking
to the bottom while the lighter material floats, hence why water is above earth, air above water and
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
64
earth, fire above all three, continuously for all the configurations of matter.
The Epicurean epistemology of Empiricism was upheld by Lucretius, claiming to base his
primary physical understanding of the world on what he sees and witnesses via study and not merely
deduction. He uses his observations to make arguments about the importance of humans over other
species, in particular noting the common maternal instinct among mammals (including humans). He
also observed, to a minor degree, the development of species but did not see them interconnected.
But neither were there Centaurs (Monsters compounded of animals of
different species never could have existed, for the growths of the various
animals are not parallel), nor at any time can there be animals of twofold
nature and double body, put together of limbs of alien birth, so that the
power and strength of each, derived from this parent and that, could be
equal.” (Lucretius, 1948)
The Epicurean ideology on the ethics of sustainable pleasure persisted. The reasonable pursuit
of pleasure still holds close to the Epicurean Morality, assisting its practitioners in living wisely and not
fruitlessly. In fact, the number of Epicurean communities swelled greatly across the Roman civilization
and, in their own way, unintentionally may have influenced certain aspects of Christian monasticism.
Like the Christians that would supplant these Socratic philosophies in Rome, the Epicureans advocated
for a quiet life spent in intellectual seclusion, study, and reflection, along with a rejection of the many
stresses of life that still afflict humanity today. These afflictions manifesting in the great stress for
survival, the need for ever improving living standards, struggles for social acceptance and recognition,
the hunger for fame and fortune, the unnecessary dealings with the malicious, and many more. In these
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
65
communes the Epicureans tucked themselves away and focused on simple, honest work that they could
manage themselves, even if it wasn't especially prosperous or luxurious.
Unlike Christian ideology, the Epicureans were imminently focused on life and maximizing the
pleasure therein. They saw that living sensibly let them avoid unnecessary hardships and stress, that
their communes filled with other intellectuals and philosophers was mentally stimulating and good for
the psyche, that the common moral interest allowed for them to engage with agreeable and trustworthy
people that they would be happy to call friends, and that they would gain greater satisfaction in having
reasonable aspirations with personal labor (such as gardening, simple manufacturing, study). It was
truly a life to be envied.
Skepticism: Academic
It was in Rome where the Academic Skeptics petered out, being replaced more firmly with the
Middle Platonists and then the Neoplatonists. Even in Rome the Academic Skeptics remained a
negative philosophy and a standard mode of operation for its practitioners to actively doubt, undermine
and prove weak the positive propositions of others. While this is good for academics, receiving untold
number of contradicting theories from naturalists, philosophers, and other scholars, in order to test the
mettle and worth of their theories they would need to be tested by a more radical and concentrated
skepticism.
In the same way that the Greek Academic Skeptics were a negative philosophy, lacking positive
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
66
or assertive aspects to their ideology other than systemically doubting all propositions presented before
them, the Roman Academic Skeptics operated. It is due to this that there will be no representative
selected for the school.
Skepticism : Pyrrhonian
Pyrrhonism, while arguably the least populous it managed to survive in the Roman territories
and expand its seeking of Eudaimonia via what they called ‘ataraxia’ (imperturbability). Along with
accepting the unknown and unknowable to ease the human psyche there were exercises in both logic
and epistemology to be explored by the Pyrrhonian and with the addition of later 'modes' or
manifestations of documented skepticism.
The representative of the Pyrrhonian school of Skepticism will be Sextus Empiricus. The
reasoning for this choice is because Sextus Empiricus is very likely the sole reason as to why Pyrrho's
philosophies continued into the Roman civilization and are remembered to this day, despite their lack
of mass recognition or popularity. Sextus Empiricus was a Roman physician and Philosopher, using his
philosophical understanding to better hone his ability as a medical practitioner.
Sextus Empiricus, while being a skeptic and Pyrrhonian, did advocate for the use of empiricism
in his work. Unlike radical skeptics, the Pyrrhonian skeptics advocated a mediated and lived
skepticism, by which I mean using skepticism as a foundation for further inquiry to prevent
presumptuousness or over indulgence in baseless postulation or unfounded deduction. “Sextus tells us
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
67
that the distinctively Skeptical ability is the one which enables its possessor to set out oppositions of
such a sort that suspension of judgment ensues (tranquility, we learn later, will follow ‘fortuitously’”
(Morison, B., 2014) The reasoning behind the advocation of Empiricism versus another epistemology,
like Rationalism, is again rooted deeply in the skeptical aspect of Pyrrhonism. With Rationalism it
would require increasing branches of deduction with a basis on understanding, inflection, or insight,
while Empiricism is more immediate. Immediate understandings based on immediate appearances.
Additionally, Pyrrhonism allows for a detached approach and disassociation between observer and the
observation by employing a fallibilistic mentality. Fallibilism being in regards to epistemology, there is
no way to completely justify any knowledge in its entirely. This mentality would be supported in the
modern philosophic forum by David Hume.
The association between Sextus' medical practice and his philosophy was constructive, thanks
to personal experimentation and direct witnessing of proof. Instead of having conjecture on what may
substantiate physical bodies Sextus would derive his work on that which he had the greatest faith in, his
own witnessed and noted phenomenon and experiences. It was the skeptical doubt in other theories
about the basis of human anatomy and physiology that allowed him to have a more lived and
immediate perspective, seeing how different attempted cures and reagents would alter the body. This
was likely to end up more efficient than the medical theories of the time, such as the teachings of
Hippocrates and Galen’s theory of Humours, having it replaced with personal experience as to what
works.
As before, the ethical doctrine for the Pyrrhonians is lacking, limited to introspective ethics. It
gives one’s better means of handling themselves and information, offering means of action and
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
68
conduct, rather than edicts on what basis one should handle others. In that way it stands apart from the
other Socratic/Eudaimonic schools, which had a much stronger moral focus (as Socrates himself did).
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
69
Comparing Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome
After examining in depth the various philosophies of Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome there
needs to be a comparison. The comparison will cover both differences within schools and between
schools. Considering the possibility of many schools and ideologies began as Pre-Socratic and
eventually influenced or became Socratic schools the distinction will no longer be held. While certain
philosophies have influenced many others the focus for this section will be the most direct lineage or
succession of the earliest form of the philosophy. There will also be philosophical overlap with lineage
because many philosophies effectively merged in order for their successor schools to be formed. The
clearest and cleanest example of this being the interaction between the Pythagoreans and the Platonists
(with the influence of the Stoics and Aristotelians) with regards to the Middle Platonist,
Neopythagorean and Neoplatonist schools. Because of this the information will be presented as needed
for each section.
The Metaphysical/Physical Theories and Distinctions – Various Other Schools
The majority of the many Metaphysical/Physical focused schools of Philosophy in Ancient
Greece did not survive the carry over to Rome. These schools were inherently limited in scope,
focusing primarily on cosmological and metaphysical or physical theories to describe reality and its
operations while many others would come about with ethical, logical, epistemological or aesthetic
claims as to substantiate themselves. While their decline inevitably came, their work did endure. Many
of these Pre-Socratic Schools had succeeding schools that adopted aspects of their ideology,
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
70
incorporating these elements of their ideology with their own.
This is especially prominent with the Eleatic school of Parmenides. Considering the stance that
Socrates and the Platonic schools took regarding their metaphysics/physics and even the stance put
forward by the Pythagoreans it would be unfair and inaccurate to simply conclude that these ideologies
perished and had no subsequent influence. In particular the theories of the Eleatic with the focus of
'The One', a term which will be very important in Neopythagoreanism and in Neoplatonism.
Atomist School - Epicurean
The key belief of Ancient Greek Atomism is that reality is comprised entirely of Matter and
Void. Epicureanism, founded after Atomism, shared this belief. While the influence of the Atomists on
Epicurus and Epicureanism is clear, there is key differences that have ramifications for the
philosophies.
The differences can be summarized regarding the believed properties of matter. The first is
known simply Epicurus attributing one additional property to Matter, that of weight. Democritus
applied the traits of size, shape and resistance to matter, in contrast to the elemental basis of the various
'Arche' put forward by the Metaphysical/Physical schools. This theory of weight comes from the
tendency of matter to go ‘downward’
Aristotle, however, criticizes Democritus on this point, saying that
Democritus has not explained why it is that atoms move at all, rather than
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
71
simply standing still. Epicurus seems to be answering this criticism when
he says that atoms do have a natural motion of direction--'downward'--
even though there is no bottom to the universe. This natural motion is
supposed to give an explanation for why atoms move in the first place.
Also, Epicurus thinks that it is evident that bodies do tend to travel down,
all else being equal, and he thinks that positing weight as an atomic
property accounts for this better than thinking all atomic motion is the
result of past collisions and inertia.” (O’Keefe, T., n.d., Epicurus
(341―271 B.C.E.)).
Considering a later Epicurean, Lucretius, suggests that the world is flat there are questions opened as to
whether or not this notion of “Downward” references something universal or acts as a ancestral theory
towards some kind of notion of gravity. The second difference is that Democritus claimed that sensible
qualities in matter were only subjective, not inherent to the matter itself. Epicurus agrees that while
such qualities, such as color or taste, do not exist on the atomic level. He instead applies that while
these qualities are not inherent to the individual atoms, the way matter is configured is significant and
has inherent properties. This recognition of congregations and configurations is important, and is
something that physicalist and even dualist philosophers will have to grapple with long after the time of
Democritus and Epicurus.
Lastly, but most significantly, Epicurus applied a quality called ‘The Swerve’. This property of
matter from the stance of Epicurus. According to the weight principle matter is naturally inclined to
descend. The Swerve Principle is thatIn addition to the regular tendency of Atoms to move downward
… occasionally, and at random times, the atoms swerve to the side.(O’Keefe, T., n.d., Epicurus
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
72
(341―271 B.C.E.)).. The first reason for this theory is to provide reason as to why atoms collide with
one another. If they only even fell downwards they would not collide so much as they would
accumulate, like a dune of sand. The Swerve Principle allows for atoms to shift, collide, and form
larger configurations which eventually serve to form all of the configurations of matter that a human
witnesses possible, along with humans themselves. The more interesting reason for the necessity of this
principle of randomly shifting is to preserve human freedom.
The second reason for thinking that atoms swerve is that a random
atomic motion is needed to preserve human freedom and 'break the bonds
of fate,' as Lucretius says. If the laws of atomic motion are deterministic,
then the past positions of the atoms in the universe, plus these laws,
determine everything that will occur, including human action.” (O’Keefe,
T., n.d., Epicurus (341―271 B.C.E.)).
The preservation of human freedom is absolutely necessary in the maintenance of a moral system since
morality, namely the study of making the right and ethical choices, exist only if choices exist.
This inclusion is an admittedly noble attempt to preserve human freedom, though one that
unfortunately falls short of its attempts. Even if the completely random swerving of atoms do allow for
variance to occur away from the sheer determinism as a byproduct of a mathematical and materialist
understanding of reality, it does not necessarily equate to legitimate freedom. Considering human
freedom would need the condition of humans being able to direct themselves to any real degree outside
the confines of strict determinism, this would not be an introduction of a compatibilist view. While this
may be a very early attempt at it, the random swerving does not show human freedom, it merely shows
random movement. The only way it would show human freedom is if the seemingly random swerving
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
73
could be orchestrated by human willpower, somehow. Considering that Epicurus in his discourses on
the philosophy of the mind, he makes it very clear that only bodies can interact with bodies, being
matter interacting with matter, and as such it would be bound to the same natural laws that dictate all
other forms of matter. This is further emphasized by his understanding of death as destruction of the
self, while an idealistic or metaphysical stance would have minds in the form of souls more likely to
persist of be necessarily infinite.
Another fundamental difference is the existence of an explicit ethical system between Atomism
and Epicureanism. With the Epicurean priority being set on the maximization of the greatest kind of
pleasure over the course of a lifetime the Epicureans almost seem to embody a pseudo-
consequentialistic mentality of ethics, rather than the more standard virtue ethics of the time. Atomism,
like many of the other Pre-Socratic, did not have a common ethical stance across the school. This is
especially the case considering their metaphysical stance which supposes a deterministic reality. In the
absence of choice there can be no system of morality and ethics, considering such things are the art of
determining the moral goodness or evil inherent to choices. The development of the Epicurean attempt
to disprove determinism while remaining a school that focuses on the materialism of reality allows it to
operate with an ethical system, considering they do believe in choices.
Pythagoreanism Neopythagoreanism and More
The main shift between the Pythagoreans and the Neopythagoreans in the Roman civilization is
that caused by exposure. The original Pythagoreans arose before the existence of the Socratic schools
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
74
of Platonism, Middle Platonism, Aristotelianism in the form of Peripateticism, and Stoicism. While
they did have contemporaries, such as the Eleatics, the Ionians, and the Atomists, each having such a
limited reach allowed for exposure to be fairly minimal. Thanks to the incredible popularity of the
Socratic schools, especially after the death of Socrates, and even more so in the Roman civilization,
such exposure became an inevitability.
Even though space in the public awareness was fiercely combated over, the Pythagoreans
managed to remain relevant, unlike so many other Pre-Socratic schools. One thing that remained
constant between these two schools is the worship and reverence of their founder, Pythagoras, often
revering as though he were divine.
Because of the belief in the centrality of the philosophy of Pythagoras,
later philosophy was regarded as simply an elaboration of the revelation
expounded by Pythagoras; it thus became the fashion to father the views
of later philosophers, particularly Plato, back onto Pythagoras.”
(Huffman, C., 2014)
This religious fanaticism could be what allowed for this philosophy to survive within the Roman
civilization, one which was filled with various spiritual and religious organizations and the worship of
manner mysteries.
The metaphysical stance of the Neopythagoreans is more explicit and refined in comparison to
that of the Pythagoreans. It is in that way that it acts as a predecessor to the Neoplatonists. With the
Platonic influence prominent, there came a metaphysical understanding hauntingly similar to that of the
Eleatics. This understanding came through a combination of a metaphysics and ethics, leading to a
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
75
theory that would act as a predecessor to the Neoplatonist's ‘The One’. In a stark comparison to that
made by Socrates at the end of the Republic, there was a connection between the highest and greatest
level of reality and the highest and greatest level of morality.
The sun, taking its place as the supreme level of existence and enlightenment in the Allegory of
the Cave, takes on a more literal stance. While ‘The One’ does not literally operate in saying that stars
or other celestial bodies are inherently moral or more real than any other existing thing, it does state
that in the ascent towards the greatest level of reality is also a moral ascent. Compare those trapped
within the titular cave of the Allegory to those outside of the cave, basking in the sunlight and
witnessing true forms. The Socratic comparison is put forward as a difference between those trapped by
societal mechanisms and conditioning (those within the cave) and those who break from such
conditioning and presuppositions (those who leave the cave). In the eccentric manner expressed by
their Pre-Socratic predecessors, the Neopythagoreans took this allegory to manifest itself more literally.
Instead of being an allegory of merely social interactions and the pursuit of knowledge, it would hold
metaphysical claims. This would be the perfect fertile soil in which the Neoplatonist hierarchy of
reality vs deception would arise.
While there is this difference between the Pythagoreans and Neopythagoreans, the importance
and perfections of numbers remains key. This theory fit well with the metaphysical idealistic nature of
the realm of forms, as presented by Plato. The mathematical and numeric aspect of their philosophy
was justified to them via their appreciation of astronomy and astrology, witnessing celestial bodies as
operating on numeric principles, and as such believing such principles to apply to all things. It is
because of this that the Pythagoreans and Neopythagoreans both had members that attempted to
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
76
understand physical interactions on a mathematical basis. While this is the case, there is a deep and
pervasive spiritualism and mysticism to the philosophies.
Another fundamental aspect of Neopythagoreanism is the relationship between the body and the
soul. Much like the Pythagoreans, the Neopythagorean held onto an air of mysticism, focusing on
spiritual purity via meditation, living under a code of conduct, and other such ritualistic operations. The
Pythagoreans did have a focus on the nature of the soul, which justified certain actions of theirs,
namely their veganism and refusal to eat beans (in worry that beans and humans shared a similar soul).
It is this attempt to keep the soul pure and allow them to experience a higher level of reality that formed
the Pythagorean system of ethics. In this way there is parallel to eastern spiritualism and philosophy
(superficially, at the very least). This could be explained by exposure to Gymnosophists, which some
Greek philosophers and western thinkers were exposed to at the time. Exposure to Eastern ideologies
became increasingly prevalent with the western empires, particularly that of Alexander the Great and
his conquest of the Middle East and Northern India, and that of the Roman Empire.
Sophists - Eclectics
While the Sophists may not have a proper philosophical descendancy to the Eclectics, there is
still a very firm argument of the same general ideology being applicable to both. This ideology could
be described as a general sense of Pragmatic Subjectivism. It is in this spirit of Pragmatic Subjectivism
that both have arisen.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
77
Examine the Sophists that Socrates so vehemently struggled against. They established
themselves widely as tutors in Ancient Greece, teaching the sons of wealthy families about various
topics: mathematics, history, business, and philosophy. They didn't have the type of rigorous and
academic nature that Socrates had in his pursuit for truth, attempting to understand reality in an
objective way. Their proclamations to wisdom and knowledge is what brought Socrates to examine
them in the first place, while he remained humble (or, as some of his interlocutors attested, merely
pretended humility). It is in this way that the Sophists arose, seeking cultural and seemingly superficial
knowledge and expertise in order for economic and political gain, rather than the more 'pure' pursuit of
knowledge that the philosophers would undertake.
Compare this to the Eclectic school. The Eclectic school is unified only by its selective
approach towards philosophy, as exemplified by Cicero. Cherry-picking and choosing useful or popular
philosophical theories and incorporating them into a single system, regardless of their cohesiveness,
due to personal preference or benefit. This would be extremely valued in the Roman civilization,
considering their meritocratic and pragmatic culture and approach to life. Rather than developing a
complete, coherent and cohesive ideological system in order to give explanations for natural and
societal phenomena, as other philosophical schools attempted, they approached philosophy with this
distinct Pragmatic Subjectivism. Instead of worrying about objective truths, or seeking out legitimate
knowledge, their focus was solely on how they ideology either appealed to them or how it could assist
them.
It is in this way that the Sophists and the Eclectics seem to be mirrors of one another, altered
due to the exposure to many cultures, philosophies, ideologies and religions prevalent in Ancient
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
78
Rome, in comparison to the relatively more isolated and purist Ancient Greece. The Eclectic ideology
also applied to various other forms, not just philosophy. It may be due to this Eclecticism that the
Roman civilization served as such a great means of exposure between the philosophers, having its
members more subject to looser interpretations of doctrine and previous theory, and allowing them to
create within a more diverse environment.
Socratic and Platonic Philosophy – From Athens, to Rome, and preparing to leave Antiquity
Following the life of Socrates and the rise of Plato as the premiere philosopher of Ancient
Greece, the establishment of the Platonic Academy in Athens, and the rise in popularity and acclaim of
both it and the philosophy put forward within, labeling the influence of this philosophical school as
immense would be a disgraceful understatement. While it is not the case that Socrates founded the
pursuit of philosophy, and nor did Plato, they left indelible marks on the field. The fact that from
Socrates' own philosophy at least 6 others came into being and drastically shaped the pursuit of
knowledge and human understanding forever is a testament to its weight. This is without even
considering the fact that the main competition to Platonism, being Aristotelianism, Stoicism, and
Epicureanism, were all descendants of it.
Due to Plato's efforts to outline and extrapolate on the wisdom put forward by Socrates, all the
writings of Plato, including what he references to be from Socrates, will be considered Platonism. Like
all good intellectual ventures, Platonism was open for discussion and willing to take on all opposition.
This, for better or worse, allowed the philosophy to naturally develop and change in response to the
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
79
exposure and influence that came to it.
In the early Academy, before the Roman civilization conquered the Greek civilizations, the
Platonic school had a squared focus on Academic Skepticism. This focus came from Socrates and his
constant pursuit in understanding his title of wisest man, put upon him by a god through an oracle. This
pursuit outlined the majority of Socrates' life and the entirety of why he is remembered. As such this
skepticism is reflected in Platonism well, though Socrates did have his own positive theories. Like the
earlier parts of Socrates' career, the Platonic Academy remained primarily focused on investigation
rather than enforcing their own beliefs. This is not to mean that Plato did not have positivist ideology,
for he did, but the focus was on the investigation and pursuit of knowledge.
Following the early days of the Academy, once the Romans conquered Athens, the academy
took a stronger turn towards positivist philosophy. This was when the Platonist school adopted the
unofficial stance of Middle Platonism. With the influence of Plutarch aspects of the Peripatetic school,
the Stoic school, and the Pythagorean school were incorporated within Platonism. As a consequence
there was a greater focus on metaphysical study that could be more easily classified as pseudo-religious
or theological in nature. There was increased interest in daemonia (spirits, extraphysical or supernatural
beings), the nature of souls, and the nature of God. In turn the Middle Platonists influenced the
Pythagoreans, developing them into Neopythagoreanism, a drift away from the convictions and work
of their founder but keeping very much in the spirit.
Following Middle Platonism in the Platonic Academy came Neoplatonism, which was headed
by Plotinus. His influence on the philosophy was so great that it is sometimes referred to as ‘Plotinism’
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
80
in his honor. While still very much a descendant of the Middle Platonism, it was much more elaborate,
refined, and metaphysically complex. The philosophies that influenced this were the Peripatetics, the
Stoics, and the Neopythagoreans.
The result of this effort was a grandiose and powerfully persuasive
system of thought that reflected upon a millennium of intellectual culture
and brought the scientific and moral theories of Plato, Aristotle, and the
ethics of the Stoics into fruitful dialogue with literature, myth, and
religious practice.” (Wildberg, C., 2016)
It was this philosophy that would act as an intellectual and philosophy foundation for Early Christian
philosophy, particularly having an influence on St. Augustine of Hippo. The focus of this school was
deeply and complexly metaphysical, wanting to understand reality at its essence and to figure out the
path of enlightenment in a more literal way. While this may seem at odds with the original Socratic
focus in skepticism and shifting society, it was reflect some of its influences (from the Eleatic school
and the Pythagorean school), and exists as a more literal interpretation of some of Socrates' parables
(especially the Allegory of the Cave, the discussion on reincarnation at the end of the Republic, and
much of what was discussed in the Phaedo). This investigation of the metaphysical substructure of
reality involved outlining the descent from perfection to absolute imperfection, from ‘The One’ to
Matter, and an explanation as to how to ascend, become enlightened and better oneself. In many ways
this could be seen as reflecting certain Eastern and Asian ideological traditions. It is here where the
Platonic ideology comes to an end in Antiquity before the eventual collapse of the Roman Empire and
rise of Christianity.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
81
Aristotelian/Peripateticism Influenced many
While the Peripatetic school of Aristotelians did not deviate far from the works and writings of
Aristotle and did not inspire the same following in the early European civilizations as it would in the
Middle-East, it was nonetheless influential. It's continued existence side by side with Platonist,
Stoicism, Epicureanism and Pythagoreanism allowed for exposure between all of these ideologies.
Unlike some other philosophies, who were more keen in taking advantage of this exposure in order to
develop the philosophy further, the Peripatetics seemed to be take a much more isolated route.
Consider the two greatest Aristotelians between the Greek civilizations and the Roman
civilization: Aristotle and Alexander of Aphrodisias, respectively. The main contribution given by
Alexander of Aphrodisias to the Peripatetic school of Aristotelian philosophy is not his own treatises,
but rather commentaries made on the works of Aristotle and his attempts, along with his peers, to
preserve Aristotle's works through translation and transcribing.
The Aristotelian philosophy did influence Platonism, in the form of Middle Platonism,
Pythagoreanism, in the form of Neopythagoreanism, and eventually the Peripatetic school was
subsumed by the rise of the Neoplatonists. Their influence was not forgotten, finding revitalized
interest in the Aristotelian philosophers in later history.
Considering Aristotle's prolific career, and his vast scope, covering the physical sciences, the
social sciences, and every single philosophical domain, and his devoted following his works became
immediately influential and had lasting impact throughout Europe and the Middle East. Many of his
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
82
scientific theories were put into practice, especially following antiquity, his design of the art of rhetoric
was implemented vastly, and many of his political and societal treatises influenced the shaping of
nations.
Cynicism From Greece to Rome
The Cynical School remained relatively consistent across time. This could be due in part to the
sheer simplicity of their ideology, considering they lack general theories regarding most of the types of
philosophy, instead focusing on virtue and ethics. This could also be in part to the lack of written pieces
from any of their members. This is due to the fact that a major tenant of Cynicism is the rejection of
material wealth and goods aside from that which they deem strictly necessary. One famous story
exemplifying this is Diogenes' rejection of a cup, as recalled earlier.
Though there may be additional, unforeseen repercussions of the lack of literature from Greek
and Roman Cynics. This manifests in their individual attitudes. While the ascetic nature, the tendency
towards self reliance, and the fixation on virtue are universal, other aspects are less shared.
Demonax, the cynical philosopher from Cyprus, is being used as a Roman comparison to the
earlier Greek Cynicism. Despite the fact that Demonax is not from Rome or the Italian peninsula, he
was born and raised under Roman rule and centuries after the foundation of the Cynic school and the
death of Diogenes. Unlike most Cynical Philosophers, Demonax is depicted as being kindly and greatly
loved by the people.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
83
Diogenes of Sinope, like his mentor Antisthenes, were known for being caustic. Antisthenes,
one of the many followers of Socrates, likely developed it due to Socrates. Not that Socrates was
known for being caustic or bitter in his rhetoric or his handling of others, he did mention explicitly the
utility of bitterness or unpleasantness of certain necessary persons. Socrates spoke of a hypothetical
situation in The Republic where the people had to choose a ruler or ally, either a doctor or a provider of
sweets, and from their appearance alone the doctor provided bitterness and harm and the sweets
provider gave pleasure and joy, and would be selected every time, to the harm of the civilians. This
carried over to Cynical philosophy, using bitterness towards the unvirtuous to bring about virtue in the
long run. Unlike Diogenes, who was both ridiculed and respected, Lucius recounts Demonax as having
a very positive relationship with his society. It would be considered an honor to house him or feed him
for the night. According to various anecdotes and recountings both Antisthenes and Diogenes of Sinope
were harsh against everyone, especially so to those who would attempt to walk their path.
42a When someone expressed a wish to study philosophy with him,
Diogenes gave him a fish to carry and told him to follow in his footsteps;
the man threw it away out of shame,* and when Diogenes ran across him
again some time later, he burst out laughing and said, ‘Our friendship
was brought to an end by a fish!’ (Diogenes Laertius 5.36; G367)” (Hard,
R., 2012, p.17)
In comparison the people of Athens held Demonax in reverence, and Lucian spoke highly of him.
Other than this difference between the two representatives of the Cynics, which would account
for a great deal in how memorable and noteworthy they were as people since Diogenes is known
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
84
commonly more for his wit and shameless audacity, the overall lifestyles of these philosophers seemed
very similar. Namely living simply, eating simply, having very little, and trying to live as minimally as
possible. According to Lucius, Demonax even starved himself to death.
65 When he found that he was no longer able to take care of himself, he
repeated to his friends the tag with which the heralds close the festival:
The games are done, The crowns all won; No more delay, But haste away,
and from that moment abstaining from food, left life as cheerfully as he
had lived it.” (Hard, R., 2012, p.20)
This keeps in line with the virtue of self reliance cherished so dearly by the Cynics. Having to
live in complete reliance to others, needed to be actively tended to, would be unacceptable. Maybe this
would been the circumstance needed to convince Plato that Cynicism was not ‘Socrates gone mad’.
134b When someone asked him, ‘What sort of man do you consider
Diogenes to be?’, he [Plato] replied, ‘Socrates gone mad’.” (Hard, R.,
2012, p.35)
Cynicism stayed resilient to the influences of other philosophies, though it was often seen in
comparison to Stoicism. Cynicism eventually found its influence in Christian philosophy, primarily in
the asceticism and sacrifice found therein.
Stoicism From Greece to Rome
Stoicism, as a philosophy, is one of the more firm and resilient philosophies with a sizable body
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
85
of literature. It has a greater and more full sense of of understanding and completeness across the
different philosophical studies than many of its contemporaries, is a school that is valued to those of all
social statuses, and is universally appreciable to innumerable people, even of conflicting worldviews.
The founder of the Stoic philosophy in Greece was Zeno of Citium, a shipwrecked merchant
left with nothing in Athens. With nothing more to lose but his life, and with a new found passion for
the philosophical pursuit of understanding, he learned how to master himself even in the most dire of
situations. Zeno of Citium is said to have died suffocating himself after tripping, falling, and breaking
his toe, claiming that he was called and it was his time. Epictetus, author of the Enchiridion, was a
slave, utilizing this ideology to make life more bearable. Marcus Aurelius, being emperor of the Roman
Empire, was one of the most powerful men of his time, if not the most powerful. With all of that before
him he lived a life of relatively little comfort. Leading wars in service to his people and his empire, and
suffering personal tragedies, all he had as solace was his philosophy. After his death his private
writings were published to become the famous Meditations, considered one of the most influential
pieces of philosophical literature ever written. There are those who held him to such a high standard as
referring to him as The ‘Philosopher King’ that Socrates was calling for in The Republic. Seneca the
Younger's, Seneca the Elder, father was a eques, a wealthy member of Roman society with property
and access to education. In his life he even rose to the point of becoming the tutor of emperor Nero. His
life came to an end when Nero accused Seneca the Younger of plotting against him and commanded
him to take his own life, which he did, slitting his wrists open and bleeding out over a long and
agonizing period of time.
All these philosophers share a common philosophy, one that assisted them greatly in their lives.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
86
This philosophy's main tenants are that of logic, discipline and simplicity. The main focus of Stoicism
is a proper understanding of what one can control in life. This leads to a logical, introspective
investigation as to what is worthwhile for one to agonize over. To the Stoic, the only thing that one has
proper and true control over is the self: how one things and how one acts, most importantly one's
actions. The actions of others, the will of fate and the gods, the results of their own actions, and the
natural happenstances in life are completely outside of their influence and as such is not worth
worrying over. This is how the Stoics earned their reputation as being unaffected and, appropriately,
stoic, feeling that most things are outside of their reason to worry.
This pursuit allows the Stoics to live contended lives in Eudaimonia, not growing overly
attached to anything or anyone, not becoming overwhelmingly delighted or sorrowful in their loss. In
this way they could be interpreted to be numbed of life, which was not necessarily the case. There were
those who manifested their virtue differently. Seneca was infamous for his sharp witticisms even in his
dying hours, while Marcus Aurelius' writings reveal a somber and dutiful life.
This is focus on logic and ethics is not to say that the other domains of philosophy were
neglected. Unlike the ethics and logic of the Stoics, which act as foundations for all the rest of their
philosophy, their metaphysics or aesthetics did not need to be so universal. Generally their
epistemology was rather similar, a mild skepticism with an internal focus about self knowledge and
control, as driven by their logic.
This philosophy was wildly popular in Rome. Though, this philosophy was not one that
completely unique. Comparisons could easily be made between Stoicism and many ideological or
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
87
religious systems, such as Buddhism. While the Stoics didn't have the passionate nature of the Cynics,
nor their asceticism, there were also common focuses in it, regarding the complete devotion of one's
life to virtue.
The influence of the Stoics was great, but most strongly manifested in the Roman-era Platonic
school. It is with their popularity and influence that the Platonic academy move from being a school
primarily focused on the academic skepticism and go on towards more positivist doctrine. Due to the
complexity of the words of Socrates and , as a consequence, Plato both find these schools could easily
be founded, justified, and take hold within the Academy. Thanks to the Stoic influence the Platonic
school was able to develop successfully into Middle Platonism, followed by Neoplatonism. The tell tale
signs of Stoicism are there in Middle Platonism's and Neoplatonism's approach to virtue and goodness.
The distinction with the Neoplatonists is that it was not logic and reason that brought them to virtue
primarily, but firstly an epistemological and metaphysical approach to understanding that lead them to
their virtue.
Skepticism : Academic Left in the Early Academy
Academic Skepticism did not have much of a lineage outside of Ancient Greece. Their main
presence was found in the Platonic Academy, considering the separation between Platonism from the
schools that dominated the Platonic Academy.
The focus of the Academic Skeptics, being that of complete skepticism and the urge to question
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
88
and undermine all things presented to them, is a natural byproduct of the investigations undertaken by
Socrates after the Oracle claimed that the god named him as the wisest of all men. This lead to his long
career as the gadfly of Athens. While Socrates' skepticism is reflected partially in his ideology, like the
other Eudaimonic or Socratic schools the Academic Skeptics took this focus of his philosophy ran with
it. Socrates' Skepticism is best seen in a positivist stance in relation to Pyrrhonism (being a school of
epistemological skepticism), Cynicism (being a school of cultural skepticism), and Stoicism (being
very similar to Cynicism).
The Academic Skeptics, while not being a complete ideology, acting more as a Modus
Operandi for how the Academy would handle new theories. This pervasive skepticism would also earn
the school a somewhat stagnant reputation. In a way, the Academic Skeptics likely prevented the rise of
many other philosophical stances in Ancient Greece due to their primary objective being to undermine
all that brought to them, for better or worse. This is not to say this focus was not appropriate. Being a
great venue of intellectuals with all sorts of eccentric ideology (look no further than the Pythagoreans
to see how unusual ideologies may manifest!), there was an equally great need to be resilient. But, in
being very much open to dialogue and subsequently ridicule, this openness may be what allowed later
Platonism to be shaped and developed into Middle Platonism and then Neoplatonism.
The Academic Skeptics were replaced in the Platonic Academy by the Stoics, shifting early
Platonism to Middle Platonism. This change came place after the conquest of the Greek civilizations by
the Roman Empire. One major influencing factor that could have ushered in such a change would be
the Roman Culture. Less interested on sheer speculative, idealist intellectualism they would want more
positivist guidance giving active aid to their lives. Stoicism, being likely the most universally
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
89
applicable of the Eudaimonic philosophies and being immensely useful would find favor in this new
order. It is with the rise of the Stoics in the Roman civilization where the Academic Skeptics, along
with other highly skeptical philosophies such as Pyrrhonism, would come to their end.
Skepticism : Pyrrhonian – From Greece to Rome
Between Pyrrho and Sextus Empiricus, there is no noticeable significant differences between
Pyrrhonism. This may be due to a lack of literature left behind on both sides, which in turn may be due
to a lack of followers of this philosophy. Considering this being the one of the only coherent schools
seriously trying to handle the epistemological problem of knowing, it is a real shame that they ended up
like this. Either way, they earned their position among the other Eudaimonic schools.
It was more than just a questioning of what can be known that brings them here as a
Eudaimonic school of philosophy, but offering legitimate and meaningful attempts towards solving the
issue rather than the Academic Skeptics who were united only by their division and attempts to take
apart all theories of knowledge. The Pyrrhonians attempted to offer solace in the form of logical
practices and realizations to all those who came to realize the infinite imperfections in perception and
who may have suffered from existential dread due to it.
Unfortunately it would seem to be the case that the last Pyrrhonian of significance would be
Sextus Empiricus, and the school would fall by the wayside as so many others. Why would this
happen? It would seem this to not be unusual, due to the rise of a Stoic-positivist-focused Middle
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
90
Platonism rather than the Academic Skepticism that would hold the early Platonists and the Platonic
Academy in its fledgling years. It would seem that the Roman civilization and its citizens would have a
greater focus on more clear, decisive, and directive answers to their questions than pondering on the
absence that exists within understanding to the point of fruitlessness. Rather than grappling with more
abstract and seemingly useless things in this way, they desired and found assurance and firm ground to
stand on in epistemology as to lead them to what they need to do to conquer life.
Cyrenaics – Left behind in Cyrene
The Cyrenaics did not have a major following outside of Cyrene other than those who
coincidentally lived Cyrenaic lifestyles while seeking to appease their appetites. With this focus on
skepticism, empiricism and the intangibility of what is to come paired with their moral focus on
hedonism lead them with a life of indulgence. Those in Rome who cared little for the future and for
intellectual pursuits, instead seeking to satisfy the whims of their
The Cyrenaics are unabashed sensual hedonists: the highest good is my
own pleasure, with all else being valuable only as a means to securing my
own pleasure, and bodily pleasures are better than mental pleasures.”
(O’Keefe, T., n.d., Cyrenaics)
While their pursuit of pleasure can be attributed to them attempting to realize natural virtues, like the
Cynics do with self reliance and minimalism, and while Aristippus of Cyrene did engage in his share of
mental pleasures, by following Socrates, and physical ones, as recounted in many anecdotes following
him, it is clear that this philosophy was ultimately neglected.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
91
Taking up the epistemological stance of the Cyrenaics, being a high form of skepticism
supplemented by empiricism and the examination of sensation, there would be many schools to carry
this question on into the Roman civilization. Firstly would be the Academic Skeptics. While these are
more about complete and abject skepticism regarding all things without the necessary recognition of
the importance of empiricism. Taking up both the importance of skepticism and the empirical analysis
of sensation and impressions would be the Pyrrhonians, who would peter out in the Roman civilization.
Finally, the epistemological stance of Empiricism would be held most firmly by the Epicureans, who
would also take up the misapplied slur of “Hedonist”, while ultimately being far more sophisticated
than that.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
92
Conclusion
After the complete comparison between both the philosophies and representing philosophers of
said philosophies from Ancient Greece and Ancient Rome when one can fully theorize and speculate as
to what is the cause of this shift. To examine the shift more closely there is necessity to comment on
where the philosophies stood at the end. There are many factors to be taken into consideration when
theorizing why certain philosophies became prominent in the Roman civilization versus the Greek
civilization, one of the most important ones being an examination as to overall cultural values.
First, there is importance in which philosophies rose to the forefront of Roman civilization.
Stoicism and Epicureanism had the hearts and minds of the Roman people more than any other
philosophy. Why is this? It is most likely due to what they focused on, and how it would be applicable
within the Roman civilization.
Stoicism
The Stoics focused on the utilization of logic, discipline, and temperance to minimize the
suffering of life. A major facet of that is only feeling suffering or satisfaction based on things that the
individual has control over, namely their own voluntary actions. By 'their own voluntary actions', what
is meant is specifically the course of action undertaken, the result of said actions are outside their realm
of control. The machinations of other humans, the whims of the gods, the tides of nature, all of these
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
93
things and more are entirely outside of the Stoic's ability to control. As such, to a Stoic it is entirely
futile to lament the unavoidable and uncontrollable, instead for there to be a best focus on that which
they can control. A major aspect of it is the dissociation of passions and connections, something very
much expressed in Epictetus' Enchiridion. In that way it shows its ideological kinship with Cynicism,
being self-focused and self-reliant. To a Stoic the loss of their wife is not something to feel suffering
over considering they lived their life in virtue and, as such, they could have done no better. Stoicism as
a philosophy is often expressed as stoic in the form of emotions, namely the lack of emotional reaction
to events. This is not necessarily the case, for there can be discontent when realizing that one acted less
than virtuously, and satisfaction when realizing one acted in virtue.
This is not an uncommon ideology, something that manifested itself in the Eastern world as
well in the form of Buddhism. It is a philosophy that would work very well in the Roman civilization,
on all levels of its people. From the slaves, like Epictetus, to the wealthy, such as Seneca the Younger,
to even the emperors, such as Marcus Aurelius, could find solace and utility in Stoicism. The logical
emotional numbness provided by Stoicism is useful in a practical sense to all stations of life. For the
slave it makes their lives of service and abuse tolerable. For the average citizen, it helps steel against
the unpleasantness and disappointments within their lives. For leaders, it assists in ensuring that they
take optimal and emotionally dispassionate actions to ensure the best outcome for their civilization.
While Stoicism was popular throughout the Roman civilization, its main form of competition can be
considered its opposite in many ways.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
94
Epicureanism
The Epicureans and the Stoics share two major factors in common: their insistence upon the
utility of logic and their interests to minimize discomfort. The Epicureans, unlike the Stoics, do not
focus on making themselves more unfeeling and resilient in the face of life, they instead focus on a
logical maximization of pleasure. Through the use of careful consideration, discipline, extensive
planning and moderation the Epicureans focus on maximizing the overall pleasure of their life while
minimizing the pain. One could say that they seek to have the greatest 'net-gain' of pleasure across an
entire lifespan, in contrast to the more basic and hedonistic impulses of the Cyrenaics.
While the Romans believed in the Gods they were a more materialistic (interested in their
present life rather than a prospective afterlife) than other populations. They engaged in vast feasts, had
deep interests in sexuality, delighted in all forms of entertainment, indulged and imbibed in various
pleasures when possible. To such a people who were definitely not ascetic in nature the Epicureans
would offer them precisely what they wanted in life: to live the best life possible from a pleasure
perspective. Thanks to the Epicureans and their pursuit of moderation to ensure future pleasures, many
of those within the civilian ranks of the Roman Empire and higher could find this philosophy to have
great practical utility. The Epicurean philosophy would allow for them to live long, healthy and
pleasurable lives of both intellectual richness and pleasant sensations. This applies especially so to
those who lived within one of the many Epicurean communes, spending their lives in the company of
friends, engaging in rewarding simplistic labor, and sharing the benefits of bringing amicable
intellectuals together to discussions in the evening. Despite the vicious rumors initially spread about
Epicureans and Epicurus himself of debauchery, vast sexual parties, and excessive indulgence it would
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
95
be easy for any Roman to see that this is not the case for an Epicurean.
Even the Epicurean approach to epistemology and metaphysics/physics is something that all
levels of Roman civilization could appreciate. With a focus on the witnessed world and the
encouraging of experimentation based on documented and empirical discoveries the study of natural
philosophy is not something only for the highly educated but for anyone with an inquisitive mind. In
addition to the epistemology the metaphysical/physical system is relatively simplistic considering it has
a physical focus rather than a metaphysical focus. It would allow for the vast number of uneducated
persons within the civilization to better come to terms and understand natural phenomena in
demonstrable experimentation rather than metaphysical and often transcendental speculation.
Changed Philosophies
The most significant philosophical shifts came from the Platonic schools. The line of
development came from a school that was dominated by Academic Skepticism, though still had
Platonic works there, to Middle Platonists, and eventually to Neoplatonists. The most direct cause of
this development was exposure to and the creation of other philosophies. The creation of the Middle
Platonist school, a reaction against the philosophically negative school of the Academic Skeptics, came
as a byproduct of the intermingling of Platonism, the Aristotelian school of the Peripatetics, and along
with increased exposure to the Pythagorean, Stoic and Cynic schools. The Pythagoreans, in turn, took
influence from the Middle Platonists and developed the Neopythagorean school during the Roman
Empire. Lastly an additional blending of the Neopythagorean and the Middle Platonic philosophies, in
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
96
addition with some new discoveries by Plotinus lead to the rise of the Neoplatonic (sometimes called
Plotinist) school. The Neoplatonic school was not the end of the Platonic philosophies, as it would later
develop into the early Christian philosophies that would be heralded by those such as St. Augustine of
Hippo.
The important factor being that in the Roman civilization, this cosmopolitan, multicultural,
multiethnic civilization allowed for various ideologies to come together and develop in mutual
exposure to one another. The greatest example of this exposure and development came from the
intermingling of the Pythagorean, Platonic and Aristotelian schools.
Cultural Impact
It has to be understood the the civilization and culture in which these philosophies existed. The
Greek civilizations were relatively homogeneous. They had a great sense of idealism, were more
isolated from exposure to other cultures than other civilizations, and were exposed to a great variety of
different political systems. Considering they were the civilization in which the Western philosophical
tradition arose their philosophies did not experience as much exposure or develop as would happen
later in the Roman empire, and aside from the Sophists there was less interest in the instrumentalization
of philosophy for personal gain or profit. It was in the Greek civilization where a vast number of
philosophies would spawn, but subsequently die out, as can be seen most clearly in the numerous
schools with a metaphysical/physical focus, such as the Ionian schools.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
97
The Roman civilization, as a whole, had a greater focus on militarism, pragmatism, and was
meritocratic. One of the unique philosophies that arose from it not as a continuation of the Greek
philosophies was the Eclecticist school, with its representative Cicero, as a school based on isolating
traits of other philosophies and appropriating them for their own use. Cicero, while being a
philosopher, was also a politician in the latter days of the Roman Republic and as such the utility of a
practically useful, even if not entirely coherent, philosophy was much more valued than something
coherent but unhelpful in daily lived life. The useful philosophies, such as Stoicism and Epicureanism,
flourished the most, gained the greatest following and had the most influence upon the empire. The
Platonic, Aristotelian and Pythagorean schools were still there but had a greater academic and
intellectual following rather than being something that the common person would embrace and follow.
Many philosophies fell by the wayside and died out. Cynicism remained enigmatically, and
continue as it began as a pursuit of passion to the purest ascent of virtue though it would never accrue a
large following. The Cynics would exist as an ideal to be admired, but more moderately pursued by the
Stoics, though the general ascetic nature would be carried into Christianity (without nearly as much
nudity, vulgarity, and shamelessness). Even something as arguably useful as Pyrrhonian Skepticism
died out, along with the Academic Skeptics. The reason seems to be that the Roman civilization did not
have much utility for a negative philosophy focused more on intellectual perfectionism than utility.
Ultimately, Rome really did adopt the various Greek philosophers on an appreciable level. This
did not mean that the philosophies remained untouched. The Roman civilization acted as a vast forum
of may millions of people, their cultural, philosophical, theological, political, ethical, and ideological
views coming together to collide and debate with one another. In comparison to the more idealistic
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
98
Greeks, the more pragmatic Romans took value out of and reacted positively to philosophies that would
assist them in their daily life. This could be due to the necessary cultural needs to sustain an empire
versus a city state. While city states do have their unrest the need for an empire to be pragmatic above
idealistic is present and obvious, and the Roman empire set their sights ever higher as they sought to
conquer the world. This is not to say that they were lacking in intellectual merit or quality. Considering
the massive intellectual accomplishments of their civilization and its many members, from functional
developments as having a philosopher as one of their rulers, to ideologically creating increasingly
complex worldviews with vast scope and depth, they were not intellectually feeble. It is this civilization
that would assist in making permanent the great philosophies of the Ancient World and bringing it into
the future ages of human history.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
99
Bibliography
Adamson, P. (2015). Philosophy in the Hellenistic & Roman Worlds : A history of philosophy
without any gaps. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Alexander of Aphrodisias Greek philosopher (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Alexander-of-Aphrodisias
Ambury, J.M. (n.d.). Socrates (469―399 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/socrates/ Anaximenes Of Miletus Greek philosopher (n.d.).
Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/biography/Anaximenes-of-Miletus
Apollonius of Tyana (n.d.). Retrieved from
http://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Apollonius_of_Tyana Aristotle (2000).
The Categories. (E.M. Edghill, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/2412/2412-h/2412-h.htm
Aristotle (2003). Ethics. (J.A. Smith, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/8438/8438-h/8438-h.htm
Aristotle (2011). The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. (W.D. Ross, Trans.). Seattle, WA: Pacific
Publishing Studio.
Aristotle (2013). Politics A Treatise on Government (E.M. William Ellis, Trans.). Retrieved from
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/6762/6762-h/6762-h.htm
Balaguer, M. (2016). Platonism in Metaphysics. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/platonism/
Baltzly, D. (2018). Stoicism. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
100
Berryman, S. (2016). Democritus. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/democritus/
Berryman, S. (n.d.). Ancient Atomism. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/atomism/ancient/
Blumenthal, H.J. & Armstrong, A.H. (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/Platonism
Brennan, S. & Stainton, R.J. (Eds.). (2010). Philosophy and Death : Introductory Readings.
Buffalo, NY: Broadview Press.
Caldwell, R. (2014). The Other Greek Philosophers How To Be A Cynic. Retrieved from
https://philosophynow.org/issues/104/How_To_Be_A_Cynic
Calogero, G. & Starkey, L.H. (n.d.). Eleaticism philosophy. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/Eleaticism
Cartwright, M. (2016). Plutarch. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/plutarch/
Cheilik, M. & Inguanzo, A. (1991). ANCIENT HISTORY (2nd Ed.). New York, NY : Harper-
Collins Publishers.
Cicero, M.T. (1829). The Republic of Cicero.(G.W. Featherstonhaugh, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/54161/54161-h/54161-h.htm
Cicero, M.T. (2009). Treatises on Friendship and Old Age. (E.S. Shuckburgh, Trans.). Retrieved
from https://www.gutenberg.org/files/2808/2808-h/2808-h.htm
Clayton, E. (n.d.). Aristotle: Politics. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-pol/#SH7e
Couprie, D.L. (n.d.). Anaximander (c. 610―546 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/anaximan/
Crook, J.A. (n.d.). Marcus Aurelius emperor of Rome. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Marcus-Aurelius-Roman-emperor
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
101
Curd, P. (2016). Presocratic Philosophy. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/presocratics/
Cyrenaic philosophy (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/topic/Cyrenaic
Darce Balsdon, J.P.V. & Ferguson, J. (n.d.) Marcus Tullius Cicero Roman statesman, scholar, and
writer. Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/biography/Cicero
DeLong, J.C. (n.d.). Parmenides of Elea (Late 6th cn.―Mid 5th cn. B.C.E.) . Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/parmenid/
Democritus (460―370 B.C.E.) (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/democrit/
Demonax (2nd cn. C.E.) (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/demonax/
Diano, C. & Duignan, B. (n.d.). Epicureanism. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/Epicureanism
Diano, C. (n.d.). Epicurus Greek philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Epicurus
Dillon, J.(n.d.). Platonism, Early and Middle. Retrieved from
https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/platonism-early-and-middle/v-
1/sections/platos-legacy
Dowden, B. (n.d.). Zeno’s Paradoxes. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/zeno-par/
Dudley, D.R. (2019). Seneca Roman philosopher and statesman [4 BC–AD 65]. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Lucius-Annaeus-Seneca-Roman-philosopher-and-
statesman
Duignan, B. (2019). Democritus Greek philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Democritus
Duke, G. (n.d.). The Sophists (Ancient Greek). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/sophists/
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
102
Eclecticism (n.d.). Retrieved from http://www.newworldencyclopedia.org/entry/Eclecticism
Eclecticism philosophy and theology (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/eclecticism
Epictetus (2014). The Enchiridion.(T.W. Higginson, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/45109/45109-h/45109-h.htm
Epictetus Greek philosopher (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Epictetus- Greek-philosopher
Evans, J. (n.d.). Anaximander Greek philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Anaximander
Frede, D. (2017). Alexander of Aphrodisias. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/alexander-aphrodisias/ Furley, D.J. (n.d.). Peripatetic
school. Retrieved from
http://oxfordre.com/classics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780199381135.001.0001/acrefore-
9780199381135-e-4870
Furley, D.J. (n.d.). Peripatetic school. Retrieved from
http://oxfordre.com/classics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780199381135.001.0001/acrefore-
9780199381135-e-4870
Gerlach, E. (n.d.). Greek Philosophy 3: The Milesian School – Thales, Anaximander &
Anaximenes. Retrieved from https://ericgerlach.com/greekphilosophy3/
Gerson, L (2018). Plotinus. Retrieved from plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/
Gill, N.S. (2017). Atomism - Pre-Socratic Philosophy of Atomism. Retrieved from
https://www.thoughtco.com/philosophy-of-atomism-120427
Graham, D.W. (2015). Heraclitus. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/heraclitus/
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
103
Graham, D.W. (n.d.). Anaximenes (d. 528 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/anaximen/
Graham, D.W. (n.d.). Heraclitus (fl. c. 500 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/heraclit/
Graham, J.N. (n.d.). Ancient Greek Philosophy. Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/greekphi/
Greene, N. (2018). The Life of Pythagoras The Father of Numbers. Retrieved from
https://www.thoughtco.com/pythagoras-biography-3072241
Hard, R. (Ed. & Trans.). (2012). Diogenes the Cynic Sayings and Anecdotes With Other Popular
Moralists. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Heraclitus Greek philosopher (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Heraclitus
Huffman, C. (2014). Pythagoreanism. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pythagoreanism/
Huffman, C. (2018). Pythagoras. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pythagoras/
Karamanolis, G. (n.d.). Plutarch. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plutarch/
Kenny, A.J.P. & Amadio, A.H. (n.d.). Aristotle Greek philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Aristotle
Kerferd, G.B. (n.d.). Sophist philosophy. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/Sophist- philosophy
Kirby, J. (n.d.). Chrysippus (c. 280―207 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/chrysipp/
Klein, P. (2015). Skepticism. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism/
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
104
Konstan, D. (2018). Epicurus. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epicurus/
Kraut, R. (2017). Plato. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/
Kraut, R. (n.d.). Socrates Greek philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Socrates
Lane, M. (2018). Ancient Political Philosophy. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ancient-political/
Lee, M. & Taylor, C.C.W. (2015). The Sophists. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sophists/
Lesher, J. (2018). Xenophanes. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/xenophanes/
Leucippus (5th cn. B.C.E.) (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/leucippu/
Lloyd, J. (2013). Cicero. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Cicero/
Lucian Greek writer (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/biography/Lucian
Lucian of Samosata (n.d.). LIFE OF DEMONAX. Retrieved from https://www.sacred-
texts.com/cla/luc/wl3/wl302.htm
Lucretius (1948). On The Nature Of Things. (Bailey, C., Trans.) Retrieved from
http://files.libertyfund.org/files/2242/Lucretius_1496_Bk.pdf
Lucretius (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.famousscientists.org/lucretius/
Marcus Aurelius (2001). Meditations. (M. Casaubon, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/2680/2680-h/2680-h.htm
Marcus Aurelius Biography Emperor (121–180) (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.biography.com/people/marcus-aurelius-9192657
Marcus Tullius Cicero (2018). Retrieved from https://www.history.com/topics/ancient-
history/marcus- tullius-cicero
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
105
Mark, J.J (n.d.). Diogenes of Sinope. Retrieved from
https://www.ancient.eu/Diogenes_of_Sinope/
Mark, J.J. (2009). Anaximenes. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Anaximenes/
Mark, J.J. (2009). Thales of Miletus. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Thales_of_Miletus/
Mark, J.J. (2009). Xenophanes of Colophon. Retrieved from
https://www.ancient.eu/Xenophanes_of_Colophon/
Mark, J.J. (2010), Meraclitus of Ephesus. Retrieved from
https://www.ancient.eu/Heraclitus_of_Ephesos/
Mark, J.J. (2011). Democritus. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Democritus/
Mark, J.J. (2011). Parmenides. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Parmenides/
Mark, J.J. (n.d.). Epictetus. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Epictetus/
Mark, J.M. (2009). Socrates. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/socrates/
Milesian School Philosophy | Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes | Index (n.d.). Retrieved from
http://philosophy.redzambala.com/philosophy/milesian-school-philosophy-thales-
anaximander- anaximenes-index.html
Minio-Paluello, L. (n.d.). Aristotelianism. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/Aristotelianism
Moore, E. (n.d.). Middle Platonism. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/midplato/
Moore, E. (n.d.). Neo-Platonism. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/neoplato/
Morison, B. (2014). Sextus Empiricus. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sextus-
empiricus/
Nails, D. (2018). Socrates. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/socrates/
Neo-Pythagoreanism (n.d.). Retrieved from
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
106
https://www.encyclopedia.com/religion/encyclopedias- almanacs-transcripts-and-
maps/neo-pythagoreanism
Neoplatonism (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/topic/Neoplatonism
O’Connor, J.J. & Robertson, E.F. (1999). Pythagoras of Samos. Retrieved from http://www-
history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/Biographies/Pythagoras.html
O’Keefe, T. (2018). Epicurus. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epicurus/
O’Keefe, T. (n.d.). Aristippus (c. 435―356 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/aristip/
O’Keefe, T. (n.d.). Cyrenaics. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/cyren/
O’Keefe, T. (n.d.). Epicurus (341―271 B.C.E.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/epicur/
Palmer, J. (2016). Parmenides. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/parmenides/
Palmer, J. (2017). Zeno of Elea. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/zeno-elea/
Pastor, C. (n.d.). Protagoras (fl. 5th c. B.C.E.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/protagor/
Patzia, M. (n.d.). Xenophanes (c. 570―c. 478 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/xenoph/
Pennington, B. (2010). The Death of Pythagoras. Retrieved from
https://philosophynow.org/issues/78/The_Death_of_Pythagoras
Peripatetics (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/peripati/
Pettigrove, G. (2016). Virtue Ethics. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-
virtue/
Piering, J. (n.d.). Cynics. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/Cynics/
Piering, J. (n.d.). Diogenes of Sinope (c. 404―323 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/diogsino/
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
107
Pigliucci, M. (n.d.). Stoicism. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/stoicism/
Plato (2008). Apology. (B. Jowett, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1656/1656- h/1656-h.htm
Plato (2008). Phaedo. (B. Jowett, Trans.).Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1658/1658- h/1658-h.htm
Plato (2008). Symposium. (B. Jowett, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1600/1600-h/1600-h.htm
Plato (2008). The Republic. (B. Jowett, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1497/1497-h/1497-h.htm
Plotinos (1918). Complete Works. (K.S. Guthrie, Trans.). Retrieved from
https://www.gutenberg.org/files/42930/42930-h/42930-h.htm
Popkin, R.H. (n.d.). Skepticism philosophy. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/skepticism
Pyrrhonism philosophy (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/topic/Pyrrhonism
Pyrrho’s Thought Beyond Humanity (n.d.). Retrieved from
http://assets.press.princeton.edu/chapters/s10500.pdf
Pythagoras (n.d.). Retrieved from https://www.mathopenref.com/pythagoras.html
Saunders, J.L. (n.d.). Stoics. Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/topic/Stoicism
Seddon, K.H. (n.d.). Epictetus (55–135 C.E.). Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/epictetu/
Sellars, J. (n.d.). Marcus Aurelius (121―180 C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/marcus/
Seneca, L.A. (1882). Seneca's Morals of a Happy Life, Benefits, Anger, and Clemency. (R.
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
108
L’Esetrange, Trans.). Retrieved from https://www.gutenberg.org/files/56075/56075-h/56075-
h.htm
Seneca, L.A. (1907). Tragedies of Seneca. (F.J. Miller, Trans.). Retrieved from
http://www.gutenberg.org/files/57999/57999-h/57999-h.htm
Seneca, L.A. (1968). The Stoic Philosophy of Seneca.(M. Hadas, Trans.). New York, NY: W.W.
Norton & Company.
Sextus Empiricus Greek philosopher (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Sextus-Empiricus
Shields, C. (2015). Aristotle. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle/
Simpson, D. (n.d.). Lucretius (c. 99―c. 55 B.C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/lucretiu/
Smith, R. (2017). Aristotle’s Logic. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-
logic/
Thales of Miletus (2019). Retrieved from https://www.britannica.com/biography/Thales-of-
Miletus
Thesleff, H. (n.d.). Pythagoreanism. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/science/Pythagoreanism
Thorsrud, H. (n.d.). Ancient Greek Skepticism. Retrieved from https://www.iep.utm.edu/skepanci/
Thorsrud, H. (n.d.). Cicero : Academic Skepticism. Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/cicero-a/
Turner, W. (1903). History of Philosophy. Retrieved from
https://maritain.nd.edu/jmc/etext/hop.htm
What Rome really adopted from Ancient Greece
109
Van Melsen, A.G.M. (n.d.). Atomism philosophy. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/topic/atomism
Violatti, C. (2013). Greek Philosophy. Retrieved from https://www.ancient.eu/Greek_Philosophy/
Vogt, K. (2015). Seneca. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/seneca/
Vogt, K. (2018). Ancient Skepticism. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-
ancient/
Wagoner, R. (n.d.). Lucius Annaeus Seneca (c. 4 B.C.E.―65 C.E.). Retrieved from
https://www.iep.utm.edu/seneca/
Walbank, F.W. (n.d.). Plutarch Greek biographer. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Plutarch
Wells, A.F. (n.d.). Lucretius Latin poet and philosopher. Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Lucretius
Wildberg, C. (2016). Neoplatonism. Retrieved from
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/neoplatonism/
Xenophanes Greek poet and philosopher (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Xenophanes
Zeno of Elea Greek philosopher and mathematician (n.d.). Retrieved from
https://www.britannica.com/biography/Zeno-of-Elea
[The School of Life]. (2014, Sep 17). PHILOSOPHY - The Stoics [Video File]. Retrieved from
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=yu7n0XzqtfA